Theories of Surplus-Value Study Group Presentations
Crisis and gthe Theory of Markets
(la theorie des debouches)h
----- Ricardo's Theory of Accumulation
(Nov. 11, 2003 Presentation by HAYASHI Hiroyoshi)
1. The Question of the "Absolute Over-Production of Capital"
In Theories of Surplus Value Marx criticizes Ricardofs theories of accumulation and crisis. Near
the beginning of his discussion of Ricardofs theory of accumulation, Marx
develops an extremely interesting theory, and this is related to the theory
of the gabsolute overproduction of capitalh that was discussed at our
Workersf Seminar [in October]. As for the theory of accumulation,
that is the transformation of surplus value into capital, Marx, after saying
that one part of this must be transformed into variable capital and the
other part into constant capital, has the following to say:
gTo begin with, a portion of the surplus-value (and the corresponding
surplus-product in the form of means of subsistence) has to be transformed
into variable capital, that is to say, new labour has to be bought with
it. This is only possible if the number of labourers grows or if
the labour-time during which they work, is prolonged. The latter
takes place, for instance, when a part of the labouring population was
only employed for half or two-thirds [of the normal time], or also, when
for longer or shorter periods, the working-day is absolutely prolonged,
this however, must be paid for. But that cannot be regarded as a
method of accumulation which can be continuously used. The labouring
population can increase, when previously unproductive labourers are turned
into productive ones, or sections of the population who did not work previously,
such as women and children, or paupers, are drawn into the production process.
We leave this latter point out of account here. Finally, together
with the growth of the population in general, the labouring population
can grow absolutely. If accumulation is to be a steady, continuous
process, then this absolute growth in population?although it may be decreasing
in relation to the capital employed?is a necessary condition. An
increasing population appears to be the basis of accumulation as a continuous process.
But this presupposes an average wage which permits not only reproduction
of the labouring population but also its constant growth. Capitalist
production provides for unexpected contingencies by overworking one section
of the labouring population and keeping the other as a ready reserve army
consisting of partially or entirely pauperised people.h (Vol. 32, pp.
109-110)
This passage seems to correspond to the explanation of gabsolute over-production
of capitalh in Marxfs Capital. Indeed, the gabsolute over-production of capitalh is the contrary
concept to the idea expressed in the sentence: gIf accumulation is to
be a steady, continuous process, then this absolute growth in population
-- although it may be decreasing in relation to the capital employed --
is a necessary condition.h
Here it seems that Marx is arguing that the number of workers increases
as a condition for accumulation and as the transformation of one part of
the accumulated [capital] into variable capital. Without this increase
in workers, the accumulation of capital is not possible since the variable
capital that is accumulated cannot be transformed into the real elements
of production (labor power) -- cannot purchase new labor (power). In
other words, the capital cannot function. If this occurs, accumulation
is completely impossible. That is, gabsolute over-production of capitalh
is a situation in which the accumulation of capital is gabsolutelyh impossible.
This is because:
gGiven the necessary means of production, i.e., a sufficient accumulation of capital, the creation of surplus-value is
only limited by the labouring population if the rate of surplus-value, i.e., the intensity of exploitation, is given; and no other limit but the intensity
of exploitation if the labouring population is given.h (Capital Vol. 3 Chapter 15, p. 242)
Of course, even if the actual number of workers does not increase, as long
as the working hours of the workers are extended, then capital will be
able to find labor power to correspond to the increased amount of capital. In
Theories of Surplus Value, however Marx says gBut that cannot be regarded as a method of accumulation
which can be continuously used.h (Vol. 32, p. 110) How about Capital, then? The corresponding passage in Capital is the following:
gThere would be absolute over-production of capital as soon as additional
capital for purposes of capitalist production = 0. The purpose of capitalist
production, however, is self-expansion of capital, i.e., appropriation of surplus-labour, production of surplus-value, of profit.
As soon as capital would, therefore, have grown in such a ratio to the
labouring population that neither the absolute working-time supplied by
this population, nor the relative surplus working-time, could be expanded
any further (this last would not be feasible at any rate in the case when
the demand for labour were so strong that there were a tendency for wages
to rise); at a point, therefore, when the increased capital produced just
as much, or even less, surplus-value than it did before its increase, there
would be absolute over-production of capital; i.e., the increased capital C+DC would produce no more, or even less, profit
than capital C before its expansion by DC. In both cases there would be
a steep and sudden fall in the general rate of profit, but this time due
to a change in the composition of capital not caused by the development
of the productive forces, but rather by a rise in the money-value of the
variable capital (because of increased wages) and the corresponding reduction
in the proportion of surplus-labour to necessary labour.h (Capital Vol. 3, 250.)
In Capital, the question is discussed more organically (three-dimensionally) -- i.e.,
on the premise that the limit to increasing workers has already been reached,
Marx seems to be discussing the gabsolute over-production of capitalh
where a situation arises in which the production of both absolute and variable
surplus value are not possible. But the basis for this discussion
was already provided in the concept in Theories of Surplus Value.
Expressed numerically, Marx is saying the following: If the existing
capital is 5,000 with an organic composition of 4:1 -- that is 1,000 in
variable capital is expended for 4,000 in constant capital. The rate
of surplus value is 50%, so that 1,000 variable capital produces 1,000
surplus value. In this case, the rate of profit would be 20%.
How, then, would the newly accumulated 1,000 in new capital be expended. The
organic composition of this would be the same as the original capital so
that 800 would be invested as constant capital and 200 as variable capital.
Following our premise of the gabsolute over-production of capital,h however,
no surplus value could be produced.
What would the outcome be? Marx, as we have seen, says that:
There would be a steep and sudden fall in the general rate of profit, but
this time due to a change in the composition of capital not caused by the
development of the productive forces, but rather by a rise in the money-value
of the variable capital [Engels adds in parenthesis] (because of increased
wages) and the corresponding reduction in the proportion of surplus-labour
to necessary labour.h
In other words, the original capital combined with the new capital would
amount to 6,000, but the profit would remain 1,000 as before, so that the
profit rate would drop from 20% to 16.7%. Also, the gmoney-value
of the variable capitalh would increase from 1,000 to 1,200, but the surplus
value would be the same and therefore the gproportion of surplus-labour
to necessary labourh would be greducedh from 1:1 to 6:5 (in other words,
a reduction of the proportion form 1 to 0.83).
This basically seems to be what Marx is saying, but this is not the result
of gincreased wagesh as Engels says. Even if wages remain the same,
variable capital will rise (because the new capital also includes variable
capital), but since the variable capital of the new capital does not create
any surplus value the ratio between the variable capital and surplus value
changes so that there is a greduction in the proportion of surplus-labour
to necessary labour.h This is certainly not the same thing as an
increase in wages. For this reason, Engelsf addition in parentheses
to Marxfs passage here is an act that is difficult to forgive.
2. Criticism of the "Doctrine of Harmony"
Marxfs theory of crisis is inseparably linked to his criticism of the
gdoctrine of harmonyh (gtheory of marketsh) espoused by Ricardo and
Say. According to this gtheory of markets,h a commodity can naturally
find a market because sales are purchases and purchases are sales, and
moreover because the exchange of commodities can only take place through
sales and purchases. For this reason, sales and purchases are said
to not be generally split apart, and thus crisis is not possible.
gThe conception (which really belongs to [James] Mill), adopted by Ricardo
from the tedious Say (and to which we shall return when we discuss that
miserable individual), that overproduction is not possible or at least that no general glut of the market is possible, is based on the proposition that products are exchanged against products, or as Mill put it, on the gmetaphysical equilibrium of sellers and buyersff,
and this led to [the conclusion] that demand is determined only by production,
or also that demand and supply are identical. The same proposition
exists also in the form, which Ricardo liked particularly, that any amount
of capital can be employed productively in any country.h (MECW Vol. 32, pp.124-5)
Marx then quotes the following passage from Ricardofs On the Principles of Political Economy, and Taxation:
geM. Say,f writes Ricardo in Chapter XXI (gEffects of Accumulation on Profits and Interesth), ehascmost satisfactorily
shewn, that there is no amount of capital which may not be employed in
a country, because demand is only limited by production. No man produces, but with a view to consume or sell, and he never sells, but with an intention to purchase some other commodity, which may be immediately useful to him, or which may contribute to future
production. By producing, then, he necessarily becomes either the
consumer of his own goods, or the purchaser and consumer of the goods of
some other person. It is not to he supposed that he should, for any
length of time, be ill-informed of the commodities which he can most advantageously
produce, to attain the object which he has in view, namely, the possession of other goods; and, therefore, it is not probable that he will continuallyf (the point in question here is not eternal life) eproduce a commodity
for which there is no demand.fh (Ibid. p. 125)
Marx offers the following rebuttal to this view held by Ricardo:
gIt must never be forgotten, that in capitalist production what matters
is not the immediate use-value but the exchange-value and, in particular,
the expansion of surplus-value. This is the driving motive of capitalist
production, and it is a pretty conception that -- in order to reason away
the contradictions of capitalist production -- abstracts from its very
basis and depicts it as a production aiming at the direct satisfaction
of the consumption of the producers.
gFurther: since the circulation process of capital is not completed in
one day but extends over a fairly long period until the capital returns
to its original form, since this period coincides with the period within
which market-prices ||706| equalise with cost-prices, and great upheavals and changes take place
in the market in the course of this period, since great changes take place in the productivity
of labour and therefore also in the real value of commodities, it is quite clear, that between the starting-point, the
prerequisite capital, and the time of its return at the end of one of these
periods, great catastrophes must occur and elements of crisis must have
gathered and develop, and these cannot in any way be dismissed by the pitiful
proposition that products exchange for products. The comparison of value in one period with the value of the same commodities in a later
period is no scholastic illusion, as Mr. Bailey maintains, but rather forms
the fundamental principle of the circulation process of capital.h (Ibid.
p. 126)
The characteristic of Ricardofs theory of crisis is that his starting
point or basis is the gtheory of marketsh mentioned above, and that while
he recognizes the surplus of capital he does not recognize the surplus
of commodities, and only admits to a partial crisis, not a general crisis.
Ricardo and Say, on the basis of the view that sales are purchases and
purchases are sales (and likewise, although of a different dimension, that
demand is supply and supply is demand) conclude that crisis -- that is,
a general conflict between sales and purchases (commodities cannot be generally
sold, general overproduction) -- cannot occur.
In response to this, Marx raises two points. First of all, even in
the relations of simple commodity production and exchange, it is not correct
to depict this as something harmonious. And secondly, it is not correct
to understand the relations of commodity production and exchange in an
abstract manner and on such a basis conclude that crisis is not possible.
Marx also sees crisis within the relations of simple commodity production
and exchange, but that is not real crisis, but only the potential for crisis. Commodity
exchange is certainly not barter exchange, but rather exchange value with
commodities, on the one hand, and on the other hand the relations in which
money appears. Marx has the following to say about this:
gIn any case: If purchase and sale do not get bogged down, and therefore do not require
forcible adjustment -- and, on the other hand, money as means of payment
functions in such a way that claims are mutually settled, and thus the
contradiction inherent in money as a means of payment is not realized --
if therefore neither of these two abstract forms of crisis become real,
no crisis exists. No crisis can exist unless sale and purchase are
separated from one another and come into conflict, or the contradictions
contained in money as a means of payment actually come into play; crisis,
therefore, cannot exist without manifesting itself at the same time in
its simple form, as the contradiction between sale and purchase and the
contradiction of money as a means-of payment. But these are merely
forms, general possibilities of crisis, and hence also forms, abstract forms,
of actual crisis. In them, the nature of crisis appears in its simplest
forms, and, in so far as this form is itself the simplest content of crisis,
in its simplest content. But the content is not yet substantiated. Simple circulation of money and even the circulation of money as
a means of payment -- and both come into being long before capitalist production, while there are no crises -- are possible and actually
take place without crises. These forms alone, therefore, do not explain
why their crucial aspect becomes prominent and why the potential contradiction
contained in them becomes a real contradiction.
gThis shows how insipid the economists are who, when they are no longer
able to explain away the phenomenon of overproduction and crises, are content
to say that these forms contain the possibility of crises, that it is therefore accidental whether or not crises occur and consequently their occurrence is itself
merely a matter of chance.
gThe contradictions inherent in the circulation of commodities, which
are further developed in the circulation of money -- and thus, also, the
possibilities of crisis -- reproduce themselves, automatically, in capital,
since developed circulation of commodities and of money, in fact, only
takes place on the basis of capital.
gBut now the further development of the potential crisis has to be traced
-- the real crisis can only be educed from the real movement of capitalist
production, competition and credit -- in so far as crisis arises out of
the special aspects of capital which are peculiar to it as capital, and not merely comprised in its existence as commodity
and money.h (Ibid. pp. 142-3)
Against those theorists who recognized partial crisis but did not recognize
general crisis, Marx argued that when crisis threatens the main sectors
of production that is a general crisis, and necessarily is transformed
into a general crisis.
3. The Ultimate Cause of Crisis
Marx emphasizes that real overproduction and crisis cannot arise from the
relations of simple commodities and money, but rather only out of the relations
of capital. Marx expresses this idea by saying that the glimitation
of capital is capital itself.h What does this mean, concretely speaking? Marx
described over-production in the following way:
gThe word over-production in itself leads to error. So long as the most urgent needs of a
large part of society are not satisfied, or only the most immediate needs are satisfied, there can of course be absolutely
no talk of an over-production of products -- in the sense that the amount of products is excessive in relation
to the need for them. On the contrary, it must be said that on the
basis of capitalist production, there is constant under-production in this sense. The limits to production are set by the profit of
the capitalist and in no way by the needs of the producers. But over-production
of products and over-production of commodities are two entirely different things. If Ricardo thinks that the commodity form makes no difference to the product, and furthermore, that commodity circulation differs only formally from barter, that in this context the exchange-value
is only a fleeting form of the exchange of things, and that money is therefore
merely a formal means of circulation -- then this in fact is in line with
his presupposition that the bourgeois mode of production is the absolute
mode of production, hence it is a mode of production without any definite
specific characteristics, its distinctive traits are merely formal.
He cannot therefore admit that the bourgeois mode of production contains
within itself a barrier to the free development of the productive forces,
a barrier which comes to the surface in crises and, in particular, in over-production -- the basic phenomenon in crises.h (pp 156-7)
Near the end of his examination of Ricardofs theory of profit, Marx comments
on Ricardofs denial of over-production in the following way:
gSecondly he overlooks that the output level is by no means arbitrarily
chosen, but the more capitalist production develops, the more it is forced
to produce on a scale which has nothing to do with the immediate demand
but depends on a constant expansion of the world market. He has recourse
to Say's trite assumption, that the capitalist produces not for the sake
of profit, surplus-value, but produces use-value directly for consumption
-- for his own consumption. He overlooks the fact that the commodity
has to be converted into money. The demand of the workers does not
suffice, since profit arises precisely from the fact that the demand of
the workers is smaller than the value of their product, and that it [profit]
is all the greater the smaller, relatively, is this demand. The demand
of the capitalists among themselves is equally insufficient. Over-production
does not call forth a constant fall in profit, but periodic over-production recurs constantly. It is followed by periods of
under-production etc. Over-production arises precisely from the fact
that the mass of the people can never consume more than the average quantity
of necessaries, that their consumption therefore does not grow correspondingly
with the productivity of labour. But the whole of this section belongs
to the competition of capitals. (pp. 101-2)
gWhen considering the production process we saw that the whole aim of
capitalist production is appropriation of the greatest possible amount
of surplus-labour, in other words, the realisation of the greatest possible
amount of immediate labour-time with the given capital, be it through the
prolongation of the labour-day or the reduction of the necessary labour-time,
through the development of the productive power of labour by means of cooperation,
division of labour, machinery etc., in short, large-scale production, i.e.,
mass production. It is thus in the nature of capitalist production,
to produce without regard to the limits of the market. (Ibid. p. 151)
Marx speaks of the gintrinsic basis for crisish as follows:
gBut the whole process of accumulation in the first place resolves itself
into production on an expanding scale, which on the one hand corresponds to the natural growth of the population,
and on the other hand, forms an inherent basis for the phenomena which
appear during crises. The criterion of this expansion of production is capital itself, the existing level of the conditions of production and the unlimited
desire of the capitalists to enrich themselves and to enlarge their capital,
but by no means consumption, which from the outset is inhibited, since the majority of the population,
the working people, can only expand their consumption within very narrow
limits, whereas the demand for labour, although it grows absolutely, decreases relatively, to the same extent as capitalism develops. Moreover, all equalisations
are accidental and although the proportion of capital employed in individual spheres
is equalised by a continuous process, the continuity of this process itself
equally presupposes the constant disproportion which it has continuously,
often violently, to even out. (pp. 123-4)
gIt is the unconditional development of the productive forces and therefore
mass production on the basis of a mass of producers who are confined within
the bounds of the necessary means of subsistence on the one hand and, on
the other, the barrier set up by the capitalists' profit, which [forms]
the basis of modern over-production.
gAll the objections which Ricardo and others raise against overproduction
etc. rest on the fact that they regard bourgeois production either as a
mode of production in which no distinction exists between purchase and
sale -- direct barter -- or as social production, implying that society, as if according to a plan, distributes
its means of production and productive forces in the degree and measure
which is required for the fulfilment of the various social needs, so that
each sphere of production receives the quota of social capital required to satisfy the corresponding need. This
fiction arises entirely from the inability to grasp the specific form of
bourgeois production and this inability in turn arises from the obsession
that bourgeois production is production as such, just like a man who believes
in a particular religion and sees it as the religion, and everything outside of it only as false religions.
gOn the contrary, the question that has to be answered is: since, on the
basis of capitalist production, everyone works for himself and a particular
labour must at the same time appear as its opposite, as abstract general
labour and in this form as social labour -- how is it possible to achieve
the necessary balance and interdependence of the various spheres of production,
their dimensions and the proportions between them, except through the constant
neutralisation of a constant disharmony? This is admitted by those
who speak of adjustments through competition, for these adjustments always
presuppose that there is something to adjust, and therefore that harmony
is always only a result of the movement which neutralises the existing
disharmony.h (p. 157-8)
gOver-production is specifically conditioned by the general law of the production of capital:
to produce to the limit set by the productive forces, that is to say, to
exploit the maximum amount of labour with the given amount of capital,
without any consideration for the actual limits of the market or the needs
backed by the ability to pay; and this is carried out through continuous
expansion of reproduction and accumulation, and therefore constant reconversion
of revenue into capital, while on the other hand, the mass of the producers
remain tied to the average level of needs, and must remain tied to it according
to the nature of capitalist production.h (pp. 163-4)
These views are also repeated in Capital. For example, in chapter 30 of the third volume of Capital where Marx is providing the concept of gcommercial credit,h there is
a passage with the same sort of content. This is a passage that was
brought up by a MCG member at the recent Kansai Workersf Seminar. First
letfs look at the passage from the Engels-version of Capital:
gLet us suppose that the whole of society is composed only of industrial
capitalists and wage-workers. Let us furthermore disregard price fluctuations,
which prevent large portions of the total capital from replacing themselves
in their average proportions and which, owing to the general interrelations
of the entire reproduction process as developed in particular by credit,
must always call forth general stoppages of a transient nature. Let us
also disregard the sham transactions and speculations, which the credit
system favours. Then, a crisis could only be explained as the result of
a disproportion of production in various branches of the economy, and as
a result of a disproportion between the consumption of the capitalists
and their accumulation. But as matters stand, the replacement of the capital
invested in production depends largely upon the consuming power of the
non-producing classes; while the consuming power of the workers is limited
partly by the laws of wages, partly by the fact that they are used only
as long as they can be profitably employed by the capitalist class. The
ultimate reason for all real crises always remains the poverty and restricted
consumption of the masses as opposed to the drive of capitalist production
to develop the productive forces as though only the absolute consuming
power of society constituted their limit. (Vol 3 ch. 30)
Setting aside the issue that in Marxfs original manuscript this entire
passage was set in parenthesis, the final sentence that appears in Capital (gThe ultimate reasonhc) is somewhat different from Marxfs manuscript. Marxfs
original sentence is [translated from the Japanese]: gThe ultimate reason
for all real crises always remains the poverty of the masses, on the one
hand, and the drive of capitalist production, on the other hand, to develop
the productive forces as though absolute consuming power of society constituted
their limit.h
Marxfs manuscript and Engelsf revised version are gsubtlyh different. In
Engelsf version, gthe ultimate reason for all real crisesh is gthe
poverty and restricted consumption of the masses,h whereas in Marxfs
manuscript gthe ultimate reason for all real crises is gthe poverty of
the masses, on the one handh and the gdrive of capitalist production,
on the other handh so that these are seen as two opposing moments [of
crisis] in an interlocking struggle. I certainly donft think that
this is a matter of indifference.
(Translated by Roy West)
|