WPLL top-pageEnglish homepageE-mail

THEORY INDEX

A Critique of "Underconsumption Theories"

How Should Crisis Be Explained, And Has Modern Capitalism Reslly Overcome Crisis?

(From 'Prometheus' No.29 1998)

Written by Hayashi Hiroyoshi
Translated by Roy West


Contents
  1. Crisis is a Reality

  2. Marxfs Criticism of the Theory of Underconsumption

  3. Workers Under Other Capital
    (Workers as the Sellers and Purchasers of Commodities)

  4. The Contradiction Between Production and Consumption Under Capitalism
    (But not as the Underconsumption Theorists Understand It)

  5. gThe Cause of Crisish
    -gLimited Consumptionh and the Development of Unrestricted Productive Power

  6. Crisis and the Fate of the Capitalist Mode of Production

  7. The Stalinistsf Concept of Crisis
    -Mendelsonfs Theory and History of Crisis

  8. Modern Capitalism and Crisis


1. Crisis is a Reality

The consecutive bankruptcies this past year of banks and security firms -- certainly no small matter -- shocked the bourgeoisie and conservative politicians, sending them into a state of near panic while reminding them that crisis is not a thing of the past. The immediate decision to again use gpublic fundsh which had been so heavily criticized at the time of the scandal involving housing loan companies (jusen) -- but this time the sum was ten times larger -- says a great deal about the bourgeoisiefs bewilderment and sense of crisis. Since the end of the war they had continuously repeated that gcrisis is a thing of the past which will no longer occur since the management of capitalism has become feasible with the development of Keynesianism.h

Crisis, however, is indeed very real -- this reveals that as long as capitalism remains capitalism the bourgeoisie will never be able to escape their fears. They have suddenly abandoned such slogans as easing restrictions, administrative reform and financial restructuring -- these were adopted by the Hashimoto administration with great fanfare and were the gofficially authorizedh policy of the bourgeoisie -- to fall back to Keynesian expansionist policies and enlarged programs to stimulate business. This happened at the time when a critical standpoint towards Keynesianism had begun to be established following the bubble period, and the effectiveness of gsmall governmenth, financial restructuring, de-regularization and free competition (market economy) was beginning to be proclaimed. What a careless and irresponsible bunch they are!

It is not easy to say what will be the result of their change in standpoint, that is the expansionist policies to stimulate business, but it is certain that a bubble, financial collapse or a slip into inflation are all possible. The bourgeoisie believe that a bubble is of more use that a recession.

It was said after the war that crises were finished, and now there are cries that there is no escape from crises. But what is a crisis in the first place? Is it something that is unavoidable under capitalist means of production? Or can it be overcome through reforming capitalism to make it a little more humane?

Since the beginning of the 19th century when the cyclical and regular occurrence of crises became visible, many theories have appeared to explain crises and their cause. Of these explanations one which has been particularly emphasized is the so-called gunderconsumption theory.h This, in other words, is a theory that explains the cause of crisis in terms of ginsufficient consumptionh under capitalism. This theory can be broadly divided into two currents. On the one hand there is the ghumanistich theoretical current represented by Sismondi, the Narodniks (and later Rosa Luxemburg). On the other hand there is the reactionary, bourgeois (parasitic class) view connected with Malthus and Keynes. (The JCPfs position lies somewhere in between these two currents, their view is ghumanistic,h on the one hand, and Keynesian on the other, and is therefore totally inconsistent. In the end they return to the reactionary bourgeois standpoint, and this is probably inevitable. Already no essential difference can be found between their position and the Keynesian standpoint.

Simply put, the standpoint of the theory of underconsumption states that since capitalism is a society based on the exploitation of workers, the workersf consumption is also exploited and inevitably becomes gtoo small.h If workers produce but donft consume how can surplus value be grealizedh (be sold)? Under capitalism the value of a commodity appears as constant capital + variable capital + surplus value (C + V + M). The question is how is the part M realized (Luxemburgfs awareness of the problem is a little different since she asks: gWhere does the money come from for capitalists to realize the M part?h and gIsnft it impossible for capitalists to find this under epuref capitalism?h Of course this is nothing but a different kind of underconsumption theory.)

The theory of underconsumption, represented by Sismondi, was introduced to explain (criticize) the magnification of capitalist contradictions. Thus Sismondi and the Narodniks scholars had a certain positive significance in that they exposed one essential side of capitalism. However, even in their case, this theory is nonsense and is unable to grasp the essential content of capitalism. The theory of underconsumption was a reaction to and criticism of Say, Mill and Ricardofs theory of equilibrium. In other words, this was a reaction against the view that capitalism is a mode of production basically without contradictions in which no essential limitations exist that internally negate the market economy, and since production is consumption, sales are purchases, supply is demand (and the reverse as well), general overproduction or a general crisis can not occur.

Marx, of course, was opposed to the theory of equilibrium, but he also opposed the theory of underconsumption. He showed that it was based on a completely narrow and superficial understanding of the capitalist mode of production, and firmly exposed its reactionary nature. Essentially Marx explained crisis in the following way:

gCrises are never more than momentary, violent solutions for the existing contradictions, violent eruptions that re-establish the disturbed balance for the time being.h (Capital Vol. 3, chapter 15)

gThe world trade crisis must be regarded as the real concentration and forcible adjustment of all the contradictions of bourgeois economy.h (MECW Vol. 32 p. 140)

For Marx, crisis was the explosion and concentrated expression of capitalist contradictions. Marx insisted that capitalist contradictions must break out in the phenomenon of a crisis or panic because this is precisely the true character of capitalism, here lies its cause. Moreover, Marx points out that crisis is not merely the expression, or explosion of capitalist contradictions, but at the same time a violent solution, a process of forceful readjustment and the dissolution of disequilibrium.

Along with the development of capitalism, the conflict or contradiction between value and use value, production and consumption, the production and realization of value, supply and demand, etc, also necessarily develops and deepens. Simply put, at a certain stage in the development and movement of capitalism, a situation of overproduction inevitably arises where the produced commodity is not sold, cannot find a market, and the market is too limited for the produced commodity.


2. Marxfs Criticism of the Theory of Underconsumption

We have seen that one example of an incorrect theory of crisis is the theory of gunderconsumption,h but what sort of theory is this exactly?

This theory explains crisis, i.e. the fundamental contradiction of capitalism, from capitalfs exploitation of labor. Hence, it appears at first glance as a very convincing explanation.

Since this theory has a simple appearance it is extremely accessible and has the character of being easily connected with opportunism. Already during the period of the Second International, the Social Democrat Tarnoff offered the proposal that crisis could be overcome through achieving ghigh wages.h Even today this is the fixed idea and common view of the JCP and trade union opportunists.

The viewpoint of the advocates of the theory of underconsumption is simplistic. Unlike the equilibrium theorists who deny general overproduction from the simple perspective that production is consumption (demand) and sales are purchases (or purchases are sales), advocates of the underconsumption theory argue that under capitalist production sales and purchases are not in agreement because the workers are unable to buy all of what they have produced, and thus overproduction is unavoidable. Therefore, their solution is to expand the consumption of the workers and raise their standard of living. It is probably a necessity that they adopted the particular slogan: gOvercome depression through raising wages.h They argue that as wages are increased crisis can be easily overcome. However, if this were indeed so, the question arises why the bourgeoisie would be unwilling to employ such a simple and effective method. This question is either treated as an insolvable mystery or is brushed aside with the arbitrary and nonsensical explanation that gthe bourgeoisie are stupid.h

This theory at first seems quite reasonable. For example, a worker sells his labor power to the capitalist for 8,000 yen a day. In four hours of labor the worker produces products necessary to reproduce his own labor power. In other words, necessary labor is four hours (the currency expression of products objectified by one hour of labor is 2,000 yen). However, the capitalist purchased the right to use one day of labor power, and has no reason to halt labor after four hours. If he did this all of his profits would disappear and he would probably cease being a capitalist. Thus not four, but eight hours of labor are demanded and in this way the exploitation of labor is realized. Even though the worker performs eight hours of labor in one day, he only receives payment for four hours. The capitalist appropriates, without compensation, one half of the value the worker created. Since the worker only receives one half of the total value created (16,000 yen), the workerfs consumption is gtoo lowh compared to production. The worker is definitely unable to purchase 16,000-yen worth of goods with his 8,000-yen wage.

However, it should be clear at a glance that is completely nonsensical for the underconsumption theoristsf to say that under capitalism surplus value should not be realized, and that this portion (surplus) in fact represents an excess since production exceeds consumption.

The problem is easily solved. (Letfs look at the case of simple reproduction.) The surplus value -- i.e. the part exploited from the worker -- is consumed by either the capitalist alone or by others. This part is definitely not something that gcannot be soldh or find a market. Just consider the case of the individual capitalist. For example, it does not arise that the capitalist who invests 1 million yen and gets 1.2 million yen worth of commodities gcannot sellh them. Needless to say, the capitalist who invests 1 million yen and through the exploitation of workers becomes a capitalist with 1.2 million yen worth of commodities, can through the mutual exchange of his commodities ? which of course includes the surplus value -- realize the value of his own commodities. This presents no theoretical -- or practical -- difficulty. At issue for the theory of the grealizationh (i.e. its gconditions of equilibriumh) is, as Marx clarified for the mode of reproduction, only that the V + M (variable capital and surplus value) of Department I. (production of means of production) can be exchanged with the C (constant capital) of Department II. (production of means of consumption).

This is also essentially the same thing for expanded reproduction. The difference between expanded reproduction and simple reproduction is that in expanded reproduction, i.e. accumulation, materially the conditions for accumulation already exist. If these conditions have been satisfied in the production of the previous year, theoretically it is possible for conditions of complete gequilibriumh to continue to be satisfied, and it cannot be demonstrated that the realization of expanded production is gimpossible.h

For this reason Marx and Engels (as well as Lenin) necessarily criticized the theory of underconsumption.

gIt is a pure tautology to say that crises are provoked by a lack of effective demand or effective consumption. The capitalist system does not recognize any forms of consumer other than those who can pay, if we exclude the consumption of paupers and swindlers. The fact that commodities are unsaleable means no more than that no effective buyers have been found for them, i.e. no consumers (no matter whether the commodities are ultimately sold to meet the needs of productive or individual consumption). If the attempt is made to give this tautology the semblance of greater profundity, by the statement that the working class receives too small a portion of its own product, and that the evil would be remedied if it received a bigger share, i.e. if its wages rose, we need only note that crises are always prepared by a period in which wages generally rise, and the working class actually does receive a greater share in the part of the annual product destined for consumption. From the standpoint of these advocates of sound and esimplef (!) common sense, such periods should rather avert the crisis. It thus appears that capitalist production involves certain conditions independent of peoplefs good or bad intentions, which permit the relative prosperity of the working class only temporarily, and moreover always as a harbinger of crisis.h (Capital Vol. 2, ch. 20)

In Anti-Duhring Engels states that although eunderconsumptionf is as old as mankind, overproduction is a phenomenon that only exists along with capitalism. In his Theories of Surplus Value Marx also writes:

gThis was indeed also the case [underconsumption of the masses--Hayashi], and to an even higher degree, in the ancient mode of production which depended on slavery. But the ancients never thought of transforming the surplus produce into capital. Or at least to a very limited extent. (The fact that the hoarding of treasure in the narrow sense was widespread among them shows how much surplus produce lay completely idle.) They used a large part of the surplus produce for unproductive expenditure on art, religious works and travaux publics. Still less was their production directed to the release and development of the material productive forces -- division of labour, machinery, the application of the powers of nature and science to private production. In fact, by and large, they never went beyond handicraft labour. The wealth which they produced for private consumption was therefore relatively small and only appears great because it was amassed in the hands of a few persons, who, incidentally, did not know what to do with it. Although, therefore, there was no overproduction among the ancients, there was overconsumption by the rich, which in the final periods of Rome and Greece turned into mad extravagance. The few trading peoples among them lived partly at the expense of all these essentiellement poor nations. It is the unconditional development of the productive forces and therefore mass production on the basis of a mass of producers who are confined within the bounds of the necessaries on the one hand and, on the other, the barrier set up by the capitalistsf profit which [forms] the basis of modern overproduction.h (MECW Vol. 32 pp. 157-8)

In ancient society, even though there was surplus consumption, there was no surplus production. If the cause of surplus production were underconsumption, as the underconsumption theorists claim, then there should have been more violent crises in ancient society than in modern capitalist society. However, it is common knowledge that there was no crisis phenomenon in ancient society. For this reason it is clear that the theory of underconsumption is nonsense -- this is also what Marx and Engels said. Of course, this is only a negative criticism, but for the moment it is sufficient to realize the meaninglessness of the JCPfs theory of underconsumption.

Furthermore, Marx writes of an anonymous author opposed to Malthusf gprinciple concerning the nature of demand and the necessity of consumption,h whose work gcontains the essential secret of gluth even though he completely misunderstood Malthusf thought. This anonymous author wrote:

gThe very meaning of an increased demand by themh (the labourers) gis a disposition to take less themselves, and leave a larger share for their employers; and if it is said that this, by diminishing consumption, increases glut, I can only answer, that glut is synonymous with high profits.h (MECW Vol. 32)

This writer is saying that a decrease in consumption is the magnification of exploitation (i.e. high profit ratio), thus oversupply is synonymous with high profits. With these words he gleefully imagines he has struck at Malthusf logical contradictions. If one follows Malthusf argument, high profits can signify overproduction, i.e. crisis, but since high profits mean prosperity for capital, what Malthus is saying is a little strange.

This author is ironically saying that Malthus claims that workers are exploited and consumption is reduced and that this is the source of surplus profit. However, as exploitation increases, profits expand, and in a capitalist society prosperity is the magnification of exploitation (i.e. it comes from the level of the profit margin). Therefore, a market surplus has the same meaning as high profits. It is said that the rise in workersf wages will solve the contradiction through increased consumption, but increased wages means that profits will be eroded and this will cause a dilemma for the solution of the crisis. On the other hand, even if the markets for capital are expanded through increased consumption, this would reduce surplus value and thus weaken and scale back the motive for the activity of capital and accelerate the crisis. Therefore, this method is contradictory and nonsensical. This is how this author ironically comments.  Within these critical words, Marx then sees the fundamental contradiction of capitalistic production. The approach of the JCP is the exact opposite, that is, they are forever stuck in the superficial standpoint of the theory of underconsumption.

In a different place Marx said precisely the same thing when he criticized Ricardofs gdenial of the plethora capitalh.

gSecondly [he overlooks] that the output level is by no means arbitrarily chosen, but the more capitalist production develops, the more it is forced to produce on a scale which has nothing to do with the immediate demand but demands on a constant expansion of the world market. He has recourse to Sayfs absurd assumption that the capitalist produces not for the sake of profit, for exchange value, but directly for consumption, for use value -- for his own consumption. He overlooks the fact that the commodity has to be converted into money. The demand of the workers does not suffice, since profit arises precisely from the fact that the demand of the workers is smaller than the value of their product, and that it [profit] is all the greater the smaller, relatively, is this demand. The demand of the capitalists among themselves is equally insufficient. Overproduction does not call forth a lasting fall in profit, but it is lastingly periodic. It is followed by periods of underproduction etc. Overproduction arises precisely from the fact that the mass of the people can never consume more than the average quantity of necessaries, that their consumption therefore does not grow correspondingly with the productivity of labour.h (MECW Vol. 32, pp. 101-2)

Marx explained that the profit of the capitalist (today one could say company) stems from the workersf demand [the demand based on the money (wage) the worker earns from selling labor power to the capitalist] being less than the value of the products the workers create. As this demand (i.e. wage) becomes smaller relatively, profits grow correspondingly larger. For the capitalist the workersf demand is certainly considered important, but to expand this demand would require paying more and more to the workers thereby reducing profits. However, for capital the reduction of profit has an absolute limit, namely the collapse of capital itself. Capital only produces to obtain the maximum profit possible, rather than consumption being the goal of production. If profits cease then capital ceases production regardless of consumption. No matter how much demand there is for a given product (i.e. in this sense, consumption), or how much a product meets the needs of the people, if the product cannot be sold at a profit there is no demand as far as capital is concerned. On the one hand, for capital the exploitation of the workers means the reduction of demand, and capital needs to increase this demand. On the other hand, however, capital cannot expand the workersf demand and gsufficientlyh secure this demand. If this were done, profits would decrease and this would be fatal to capital. On the one hand, demand must be increased, but on the other hand, this is not possible. Here the limits and contradictions of capital are clearly revealed.

For capital, increasing profits is the source of prosperity and the cardinal premise. The expansion of profit is the same thing as capitalistic prosperity, and all other conditions being the same, the increase in profits is only possible through strengthening the exploitation of the workers, that is by decreasing the wage which is the basis of the workerfs consumption. The prosperity of capital only becomes a more certain and secure thing through limiting the consumption of the workers within all possible limits, that is, only through the ginsufficient consumptionh of the workers. Certainly the overproduction of the market -- i.e. ginsufficient consumption,h especially the ginsufficient consumptionh of the workers -- is synonymous with high profits. However, just like Robert Owen and Sismondi, the JCP is completely unable to understand this fact.


3. Workers Under Other Capital
(Workers as the Sellers and Purchasers of Commodities)

One reason that the theory of underconsumption can appear to be correct is that for capital (a given capitalist or company), the expansion of the consumption of those workers under other capital is a preferable situation since it expands the market. The spread of the JCPfs silly fantasy is based on this hypothesis.

For capital, the worker as a seller of a commodity and as a purchaser of a commodity are two completely different phenomenon. The worker as a seller of a commodity receives money (wage) with which to buy commodities. This sort of worker is important to capital as the seller of commodities since it means demand. On the other hand, in the case of the worker as the seller of labor power, the capitalist wants to control and restrict the price of the commodity (wage) as much as possible because lower wages mean higher profits, and higher wages mean lower profits. The JCP is completely unable to understand this contradiction, or the confrontational nature of the wage system.

Marx wrote that capitalists (especially those producing consumption goods) see the workers under other capitalists as purchasers or consumers of their own products, and thus as being outside the capital/wage labor relation. The expansion of consumption (i.e. increased wages) appears to be beneficial. However, essentially this is a fantasy and the capitalist becomes aware of this during a crisis. The JCPfs idea that a crisis can be overcome through increased consumption (increasing the workersf wages) is based on an absolute fantasy. Increasing wages would certainly directly increase demand for the consumption goods capitalists. However, for the individual capitalists or capital in general, increasing wages would lower the rate of exploitation and profits, and since this would in fact intensify the crisis, this is a cure (solution) that would kill the patient.

Capitalists take seriously and make a fuss over the consumption of millions of workers because they see an enormous demand. Capitalists who produce consumption goods are directly, and capitalists who produce production goods indirectly, interested in the expansion of this demand since they see this as an expansion of the market for their own products (in a sense they are correct). Ultimately, however, it is a fantasy to think that the expansion of workersf consumption (increased wages) is in the interest of capital. This is because at his own point of production the capitalist is engaged in a directly confrontational relation with the worker. In this relation (i.e. capital/wage relation), the capitalist cannot casually think that higher wages which increase consumption are in his interest. The reality of capitalist society directly appears here in the opposition between capital and wage labor. This confrontational relationship penetrates each side of the equation. The essence of capitalist society is the opposition between capital and wage labor, not their common interest. Clearly the capitalistfs hope for workers consumption is nothing but a temporary illusion, and he will soon wake up, and indeed must wake up, from this sweet daydream. Only foolish reformists, liberals, syndicalists and the JCP pick up the fantasy of the capitalists and (mis)use it for their own opportunism and class collaborationism.

Certainly in capitalist society the working class is an enormous power and a consumer class. Unlike slaves, the workers are formally (legally) an geconomich class (i.e. exchangers) equal to the bourgeoisie. Once outside of the employee relationship, the workers appear as gcitizensh independent of the capitalist class, or as the purchasers of capitalfs commodities (capitalfs beloved customer). Moreover, in capitalist society the working class as consumers are flattered with all sorts of words, and flooded with advertisements to tempt them to increase their consumption. It is plain to see that workers who appear on the market with money earned from the sale of their labor power represent a huge source of demand, and that this consumption has important meaning for capitalistic prosperity. The weakening of working class consumption is considered one of the decisive causes of capitalistic depression. However, this is simply incorrect.

This is merely a concept that comes from a capitalist looking at the relationship between another capitalist and his workers. If seen from the real oppositional class relationship that exists between capitalists and workers, this is nothing but a utopian concept or fantasy. Marx discussed how this fantasy did not grasp the essential or internal relationship between capital and labor in the following way:

gActually, the relation of one capitalist to the workers of another capitalist is none of our concern here. It only shows every capitalistfs illusion, but alters nothing in the relation of capital in general to labour. Every capitalist knows this about his worker, that he does not relate to him as producer to consumer, and [he therefore] wishes to restrict his consumption, i.e. his ability to exchange, his wage, as much as possible. Of course he would like the workers of other capitalists to be the greatest consumers possible of his own commodity. But this is just how the illusion arises -- true for the individual capitalist as distinct from all the others -- that apart from his workers the whole remaining working class confronts him as consumer and participant in exchange, as money-spender, and not as worker.h (Grundrisse, Penguin Classics p.420)

Marx next discusses the relation between the limits of consumption and crisis:

gIt is forgotten, that, as Malthus says, ethe very existence of a profit upon any commodity pre-supposes a demand exterior to that of the labourer who has produced itf, and hence the demand of the labourer himself can never be an adequate demand. Since one production sets the other into motion and hence creates consumers for itself is an eadequate demand.f On one side, this demand which production itself posits drives it forward, and must drive it forward beyond the proportion in which it would have to produce with regard to the workers; on the other side, if the demand exterior to the demand of the labourer himself disappears or shrinks up, then the collapse occurs. Capital itself then regards demand by the worker -- i.e. the payment of the wages on which this demand rests -- not as a gain but as a loss. I.e. the immanent relation between capital and labour asserts itself. Here again it is the competition among capitals, their indifference to and independence of one another, which brings it about that the individual capital relates to the workers of the entire remaining capital not as to workers: hence is driven beyond the right proportion. What precisely distinguishes capital from the master-servant relation is that the worker confronts him as consumer and possessor of exchange values, and that in the form of the possessor of money, in the form of money he becomes a simple centre of circulation -- one of its infinitely many centres, in which his specificity as worker is extinguished.h (Ibid. pp. 420-1)

Outside of production relations, in the sphere of circulation and the market, the relationship between capitalists and workers appears to be a relationship between mutually equal gcitizensh with independent rights, and a mutual relationship between a sellers of commodities and purchasers. The essential einternalf relationship between capitalists and workers (a master-servant relationship) is thus abstracted from and forgotten. The worker as gone centre of circulationh also has an important gsocial roleh (the JCP has actually earnestly used such an expression) to play in this society of capital. That is, through increased consumption the worker can make an important contribution towards overcoming the difficulties of a crisis. For the individual capitalist, other capitalistsf workers are not workers but merely possessors of money, purchasers, or gcitizensh who represent demand. Moreover, since every bourgeois regards the worker not as a worker whose consumption is narrowly limited by class relations, but merely as a possessor of money, as a consumer, and based on this premise because production is strengthened, production easily exceeds demand and must do so. If the bourgeoisie were able to evaluate the worker grationallyh or from the overall social relationships, they would not view the worker simply as a consumer, and they would know that within the confrontational class relationships their consumption is necessarily limited. However, this rational understanding is impossible for them because they are limited by their narrow-minded class-based perspective.

If a crisis arrives, however, the brutal reality of class society immediately shakes the bourgeoisie free from all illusions. They come to think of ideas, such as the view that raising workers wages or expanding consumption through higher wages is of decisive importance for profits, as optimistic foolishness or complete drivel. In other words, Marxfs so-called gimmanent relationsh penetrate their consciousness.

The individual bourgeois sees the workers of other capitalists as simply purchasers or customers for his own commodities. Therefore, he reasons that a rise in their income would mean increased demand for his commodities, and so he hopes for an increase in their wages and thinks that this will increase consumption and demand. However, once a depression worsens, and begins to have a direct effect on this capitalist, his fantasy that an increase in wages will expand demand is blown to shreds. Furthermore, in place of this fantasy the immanent truth of capitalism, its essential relations, are deeply felt, i.e. the truth of the opposition between the interests of capital and labor, how a rise in wages means a decrease in profit, how if this rise progresses without limit it would mean the collapse and end of capitalism. The view that a rise in wages means an expansion of consumption and demand provides no comfort because if there is no profit, it becomes impossible for capital to exist as capital. The essence of capital is production for profit, certainly not production for the sake of the consumption of the mass of workers and producers. In other words, capitalism is capitalism, not socialism.

Marxfs view is important since this fantasy is not only common within the bourgeoisie, but has in fact been widely circulated not only among leftwing parties, but also within the leadership of the labor unions. They insist that the increased consumption of the workers would expand the market and is thus one important -- if not the only -- means of overcoming a crisis. By emphasizing the expansion of consumption would also benefit capital through the expansion of the market, they pursue collaboration with capital and advocate the common interests of capital and the workers. While berating the bourgeoisie for not being wise enough to pursue a policy of common interest between all people (classes), they completely ignore the confrontational class relationship between the bourgeoisie and the working class. In fact, there is nothing more convenient for collaborationists than the fantasy that crisis can be overcome through increased consumption. This is the idea that the only thing obstructing this fabulous gwin-winh policy for everyone, which would overcome the crisis for the bourgeoisie and ensure wage increases for the workers, is the foolishness and stupidity of the bourgeoisie.

The Socialist Party, JCP and labor unionists should seriously ponder why the bourgeoisie would not happily carry out this sort of policy if it is indeed in their own interests. In fact, the reason is not the stupidity of the bourgeoisie or their superficial understanding. The nonsensical argument advanced that chance, misunderstanding or stupidity would prevent a policy that would be rooted in the interests of all classes and control their fate is a far cry from scientific thinking (even though the expression gscientific socialismh is often uttered by the JCP).

The JCP fails to understand the essential point that the gsystem of consumptionh has an immanent necessity for capitalism, and this cannot be removed through reforms. The attempts to change this are complete nonsense and bring about no results (in the case of the attempt to overcome a recession this effort produces the gopposite resulth). The expansion of consumption of the masses is thus a dilemma for capital. Even though this is intended to overcome the recession (through the expansion of the market for capital), this is a policy that would deepen and expand the recession (because the expansion of consumption through a wage increase would decrease profits for capitalists). Marx clearly recognized that limited consumption itself (i.e. the greatest possible limitation of consumption; that is, the greatest possible exploitation of the workers) is the basis of and starting point for large profits and thus capitalist prosperity.

An increase in workers consumption means a decrease in profit. Therefore, the dilemma is that an expansion of the workersf consumption would mean a loss of the (most important) basis of capitalfs prosperity, and the conditions for the development of a crisis would become greater. The JCP has been completely unable to gsolveh this practical contradiction thus far, and will be unable to do so in the future.

The JCP has been unable to understand that the idea that a rise in wages could expand the market and play a role in greviving the economyh is nothing but a simple fantasy, a mistaken one-sided view within the bourgeoisie. If a crisis deepens, the bourgeoisie will immediately listen to greasonh and drop this fantasy under the pressure of reality, but the foolish petty bourgeoisie (i.e. JCP) scramble to pick up this discarded illusion.

The idea that the market can be expanded through increased wages and thus a crisis -- the concentrated expression of the contradictions of capitalistic production -- can be combated, is a bourgeois viewpoint, and moreover a temporary and superficial viewpoint.

If it were in fact possible under capitalism for the peoplefs consumption to be enlarged to the point where profits were zero, then certainly all ginsufficient consumptionh could be eliminated and all crisis and depression would be finished. However, this in fact cannot and will not occur. The basis of the JCPfs politics is the incredibly sweet fantasy (suitable for the petty bourgeoisie) regarding the capitalist mode of production, which lacks an awareness that the gsystem of consumptionh that signifies the exploitation of workers is necessary for capitalism and that essentially this base of capital cannot be alleviated

Certainly if it were possible to expand the workersf consumption with no regard for profit, then it could be said that ginsufficient consumptionh in every sense could be eliminated, and capitalist recession could be solved. In that case the sublation of profit would mean that capitalism had ceased to be capitalism. However, before this stage could be reached, capital surely would have begun to counterattack. It is certainly impossible for wages to be raised to the point where the consumption limits of the workers were decisively eliminated. For this to happen the rule of capital would have to be abolished. Workers should never forget for a moment the essential limits of capital, i.e. capitalism is production for profit, not for consumption.

The fantasy of the JCP in the end revolves around the idea that capitalism is not capitalism, and production is not for profit, but directly for consumption. As a result of this fantasy, they replace the class struggles of the workers with collaboration with the bourgeoisie, and attempt to convince the bourgeoisie to eliminate the contradictions of capitalism and work together to obtain capitalist prosperity. In other words, the view that raising the wages of the workers would be in the interest not only of the workers themselves but also the bourgeoisie because the increased consumption would expand the market and thus be the path towards eliminating overproduction and overcoming the economic recession; as a result this would be a policy that would be good for all of the people. The reason why the bourgeoisie would not be aware of such a wonderful position can only be explained by saying that they are dim-witted. They believe that this dogma is the truth, and that convincing the bourgeoisie of this can save society. In fact, however, they fail to understand the reality of capitalism and have completely lost a class-based perspective, only spending their time babbling away inside their own fantasy world. Their policy would never succeed because it lacks (or has govercomeh) the awareness of the truth of class division and class struggle in capitalist society. Consequently, the gpracticeh of the JCP which is isolated from reality will inevitably collapse.


4. The Contradiction Between Production and Consumption Under Capitalism
(But not as the Underconsumption Theorists Understand It)

Just because the surplus value produced by workers is realized doesnft mean that production and consumption, or purchases and sales, are directly the same thing without any contradictions. As Marx emphasized, under capitalism production and consumption, purchases and sales, and supply and demand, while being internally united, are externally independent moments with their own movement, and herein lies the possibility for crisis to occur and develop. Already under simple commodity production and circulation the possibility of crisis developed, but under capitalistic production this develops further with the greatest opportunity for crisis being in the relation between capital and labor.

The fools in the JCP say that glimited consumptionh exists under capitalistic production. Of course! The question is not whether it exists or not, but rather what its character and significance is. The balance between production and consumption, supply and demand, and sales and purchases is obvious in the case of the exchange of products, and in the case of simple commodity production this also seems a reasonable proposition at a glance. This is because the person who receives money for selling a commodity is also the person who purchases a commodity. Under these conditions, any glimited consumptionh would be illogical. If one only abstracts from this simple relationship, one could insist, in the manner of Mill, Say or Ricardo, that sales and purchases, and purchases and sales are in agreement and that production and consumption are essentially identical, and hence general overproduction and crisis could be refuted. However, under capitalistic production, this simple argument is already completely meaningless. Sayfs theory of equilibrium, by dissolving commodity exchange into the exchange of products, ignores the historical limitations of commodity production, and thereby making possible the denial of the possibility of crisis.)

If we look at crisis in a purely formal manner, supply and demand are split and in disagreement. Commodities are supplied (produced) which exceed the demand capable of purchasing them. Here Sayfs simple theory of gharmonyh and gmarket theory,h which states that since production is consumption and purchases are sales there is agreement between supply and demand, breaks down from the start.

Marx argues that the possibility of crisis -- for the moment only a possibility ? is already given with simple commodity production and develops further under capital.

gNothing could be more foolish than the dogma that because every sale is a purchase, and every purchase a sale, the circulation of commodities necessarily implies an equilibrium between sales and purchasescBut no one directly needs to purchase because he has just sold. Circulation bursts through all the temporal, spatial and personal barriers imposed by the direct exchange of products, and it does this by splitting up the direct identity present in this case between the exchange of onefs own product and the acquisition of someone elsefs into the two antithetical segments of sale and purchase. To say that these mutually independent and antithetical processes form an internal unity is to say also that their internal unity moves forward through external antitheses. These two processes lack internal independence because they complement each other. Hence, if the assertion of their external independence [aausserliche Verselbstandigung] proceeds to a certain critical point, their unity violently makes itself felt by producing -- a crisis. There is an antithesis, immanent in the commodity, between use-vale and value, between private labour which must simultaneously manifest itself as directly social labour, and a particular, and a particular concrete kind of labour which simultaneously counts as merely abstract universal labour, between the conversion of things into persons and the conversion of persons into things [personification of things and reification of persons -- footnote in Penguin edition]; the antithetical phases of the metamorphosis of the commodity are the developed forms of motion of this immanent contradiction. These forms therefore imply the possibility of crisis, though no more than the possibility. For the development of this possibility into a reality a whole series of conditions is required, which do not even exist from the standpoint of the simple circulation of commodities.h (Capital Vol. I, pp. 208-9)

However, this disagreement between supply and demand is simply a possibility, and in normal conditions of capitalist production it does not occur. Of course, there is some possibility for this to occur partially (i.e. in the case of individual commodities or a certain sector of industry), but this does not occur in general. It might not be possible to sell a given product, but in fact they (usually) can be sold. In general a disequilibrium between supply and demand does not occur wherein too many commodities are supplied and (produced) ? or there is too little demand (purchases), which amounts to the same thing. A perpetual crisis cannot occur in capitalism. Commodities are swallowed up by the market and are able to be sold smoothly. It is an abnormal or particular case that they are not sold.

However, in simple circulation it occurs in some cases that the agreement between supply and demand and purchases and sales is lost. For example, a person who sells a commodity hoards the money from this sale instead of purchasing a commodity. This person puts a commodity into circulation, but that is all. He does not pull a corresponding commodity out of circulation. That is, instead of using the money earned from the sale of his commodity to pull a commodity out of circulation, he elects to save this money. Since we have to admit that this is not merely a random occurrence, but a necessity that can generally occur, it appears that even in the case of simple commodity circulation, supply and demand and sales and purchases are not always in balance. This is a formal possibility but definitely not an arbitrary one. Rather, it is a possibility that is inseparably and internally linked to commodity production. Under capitalistic production this occurs on an even greater scale, and appears in this production as something inevitable. Since the goal of the capitalist is normally accumulation, and accumulation is achieved through the transformation of surplus value for capital, it is an everyday occurrence that a purchase does not follow a sale. Of course the actions of individual capitalists are offset. When one capitalist sells but doesnft buy, another capitalist buys but doesnft sell. Therefore, if the capitalist class is taken as a whole it could be said that supply and demand and purchases and sales are roughly in agreement. However, even with capitalists taken as a whole, can it really be said that there is a moment or time where there are only purchases and no sales, or only sales and no purchases? This occurs in the case of the individual capitalist, but even when the capitalists are taken as a whole, can the possibility be denied that this will not be offset? Considering the capitalist class en masse, can one declare that the situation would not arise in which there were only purchases and no sales, or an avalanche in the opposite direction? Formally the possibility of this occurring could not be denied (and if this occurs it would signify a crisis). This thus signifies the possibility of crisis and its development. At any rate, it can and does occur that sales and purchases can appear as the independent moments of supply and demand, as unrelated moments.

We also know, of course, that under the system of capitalist production not only are there cases where there are only sales and no purchases, but also cases with only purchases and no sales. For instance, in the case of large-scale industries which require a long period of time to be established, a number of years are dedicated solely to the purchase of the means of production (machinery, factory facilities, etc.) In this case, no commodities are thrown into circulation for the simple reason that production has not yet commenced. It is worthless to insist that with the commencement of production the case will be reversed and sales would be greater than purchases and thus it could be said that in the end it is offset and purchases are sales and sales are purchases. Although this is probably true in the long term, if we take a given moment, there is aa decisive gap and huge difference between supply and demand, and purchases and sales.

gIf we were to consider a communist society in place of a capitalist one, then money capital would immediately be done away with, and so too the disguises that transactions acquire through it. The matter would be reduced to the fact that the society must reckon in advance how much labour, means of production and mass of subsistence it can spend, without dislocation, on branches of industry which, like the building of railways, for instance, supply neither means of production nor means of subsistence, nor any kind of useful effect, for a long period, a year or more, though they certainly do withdraw labour, means of production and means of subsistence from the total annual product. In capitalist society, on the other hand, where any kind of social rationality asserts itself only post festum (after the feast: too late to have any effect), major disturbances can and must occur constantly. On the one hand there is pressure on the money market, while conversely the absence of this pressure itself calls into being a mass of such undertakings, and therefore the precise circumstances that later provoke a pressure on the money market. The money market is under pressure because large-scale advances of money capital for long periods of time are always needed here. This is quite apart from the fact that industrialists and merchants throw the money capital they need for the carrying on of their businesses into railway speculations, etc., and replace it with loans from the money market. The other side of the coin is pressure on the societyfs available productive capital. Since elements of productive capital are constantly being withdrawn from the market and all that is put into the market is an equivalent in money, the effective demand rises, without this in itself providing any element of supplyh (Capital Vol. 2. Ch.16)

In capitalist production the stage of simple commodity production has been superseded, and thus the possibility of crisis is magnified. For example, letfs consider the relationship between capitalists and workers. Here the purchase and sale directly appear as two different things.

First letfs look at the capitalist. He must gsell at a higher price than he purchasedh. This can be said because he sells commodities which include more value than the ones he purchased. The commodities he purchases and takes out of circulation take the form of means of production and labor power (commodities as constant capital and variable capital), but the commodities he sells and puts into circulation are commodities in which the value of the means of production and labour power have been added, and which include the surplus value exploited from the workers in the process of production (commodities as the body of value in which surplus value has been added to the variable and constant capital). Of course, this has nothing to do with the arbitrary decision of the capitalist to sell the commodity at a higher price, which is merely a necessary action for as long as a capitalist remains a capitalist and a normal occurrence in a capitalist society. The motive and goal of the capitalistfs productive and economic activity is the acquisition of this surplus -- that is, to gbuy cheap and sell dearlyh gives rise to a gap between sales and purchases. For this reason, for the individual capitalist gsupplyh and gdemandh do not, and cannot, directly be in agreement.

In the case of the workers it is the same. If the capitalist doesnft buy or doesnft sell, the worker sells more and consumes less, i.e. gunderh consumes. What the worker is paid (wages, i.e. constant capital) and what he hands over to the capitalist in exchange (value) include the surplus value part in addition to the constant capital part. However, what the worker is paid is purely the constant capital part. For instance, even though the workers produces value for the capitalist of 1 million yen, they are merely paid half that amount, 500,000 Yen, in wages for the price of their labour power commodity. The capitalist receives 500,000 yen as profit. In other words, the workers are exploited. Although this part was produced by the workers, it is not realized by them. Even though the workers (through the mediation of the capitalist) put commodities with a value of 1 million yen into circulation, they only withdraw half of that in paid compensation with commodities From the workersf viewpoint the commodities with a value of 500,000 yen are a surplus. The workers gunderconsumptionh appears as an unmistakable reality. Since this phenomenon is simply accepted, the mistaken theory of underconsumption was born, this is the basis for the fact that this theory spread so easily.

Thus, under relations of capitalist production and class relations, the proposition that at a glance production and consumption are in agreement appears as something irrational because the working class cannot gpurchase,h and as a result gconsume,h everything that they themselves have produced. The workers only produce as long as they produce surplus value, i.e. as long as they produce something above their production for themselves. In other words, production and consumption only take place as long as things are produced in addition to production for the workersf own consumption, that is, production of surplus value for the capitalist. If the worker only produces for his own consumption, that is if no unpaid labor for the capitalist is carried out, no surplus value will be produced and the worker will certainly cease to work. If the worker does not produce surplus value for the capitalist, he also will not (cannot) produce for his own consumption. So as long as the workers produce, they must produce surplus value for the capitalist, i.e. labor performed in excess of that done for their own consumption, in this way they are wage workers. In this sense, the workers always produce gtoo muchh, and produce in excess of consumption. Sayfs simple proposition that production and consumption, and supply and demand are in agreement, appears at a glance to be mistaken in the case of the workers, i.e. in the case of the relation between capital and waged labor. In the case of commodities consumed individually in which onefs labor is objectified as value, not to mention those commodities industrially consumed, the workers are certainly unable to purchase all of them. Production and consumption each appear as separate, independent and mutually unconcerned moments. Here the ginternal unityh between the two appears meaningless at a glance.

Of course, this is a consequence of capitalistic production but this does not directly mean that this is gimpossibleh or gunrealizableh in capitalism (Rosa Luxemburg and Narodnik theorists often understood it in this way). Marx emphasized in the following passage that even if the limits of workersf consumption give birth to partial overproduction in the production sector of consumption goods, which leads to overproduction in related production sectors, this in itself still does not signify general overproduction:

gThis argument, however, cuts two ways. If it is easily understood how overproduction of some leading articles of consumption must bring in its wake the phenomenon of a more or less general overproduction, it is by no means clear how overproduction of these articles can arise. For the phenomenon of general production is derived from the interdependence not only of the workers directly employed in these industries, but of all branches of industries which produce the elements of their products, the various stages of their constant capital. In the latter branches of industry, overproduction is an effect. But whence does it come in the former? For the latter continue to produce so long as the former go on producing, and along with this continued production, a general growth in revenue, and therefore in their own consumption seems assured.h (MECW Vol. 32, p. 153)

This passage shows the errors of the JCPfs simplistic gtheory of underconsumptionh (the theory which explains crisis as a result of underconsumption, particularly the underconsumption of workers). In other words, Marx says that the limited consumption of workers can be understood to lead to overproduction in certain production sectors of consumption goods, but this is all; it cannot explain general overproduction. Marxfs view creates serious havoc for the vulgar view of the JCP. Overproduction in general must be explained from a different moment.

Believers in the JCPfs theory of underconsumption are completely unable to understand that in order for workers to continue their own production, and hence their consumption, it is necessary for them to produce in excess (extension of labor time) of the production needed for their own consumption (labor time), i.e. they must produce surplus value for the capitalist. Moreover, if this does not occur, even the production for themselves will not be carried out, and thus their own gconsumptionh will become impossible.

Following their pathetic wisdom, they reach the conclusion that if the workers would only produce for their own consumption, overproduction would definitely not occur since the workers would only be producing for themselves and nothing would be superfluous (JCP theorists only vaguely say that the consumption of the workers would be increased, but they donft say that this increase would make surplus value impossible). However, this is only correct if workers are understood as small producers, not exploited by capital, whose consumption is based on the sale of what they have produced themselves. (However this can only be said in the abstract theoretical meaning.)

Incidentally, the JCP claims that crisis can be evaded through the expansion of workers consumption, but do they mean to say that consumption can be expanded to any extent, and that if consumption is expanded to any extent a crisis can be avoided? If the workers were to consume all they had produced, this would be the negation of capitalist production which aims for the production of surplus value, and would thus signify socialism. However, the JCP usually posits its demands gwithin the framework of capitalism,h and hence its demand for increased consumption not only does not contradict the production of surplus value, but exists comfortably within this framework. In other words, the JCP pursues the absolutely contradictory and utopian demand of eliminating the workersf limited consumption without eliminating the very basis of their limited consumption.

Under capitalistic production relations, production, and hence consumption, can only occur as long as surplus value is produced for capital. Herein, the gsystem of consumptionh is included as an essential moment, and these relations can only be sublated by overcoming capitalistic production. On the one hand, the JCP appears to be opposed to the glimited consumptionh of the workers, but in the next breath they say that they donft deny the base of this glimited consumption,h i.e. capitalistic production, and hence approve of the continuation of the workersf glimited consumption.h Since they declare that as long as the workerfs consumption is limited recessions will continue and worsen, it could be said that they are promising the eternal existence and continuation of recession, and are defending the basis of this society.

Marx certainly emphasized that consumption is glimitedh under capitalism, not in the simplistic manner of the underconsumption theorists (the impossibility of realizing surplus value), but always as the opposition under capitalism between the productive power and the anarchical development of production. Under capitalism, production and consumption (market) are separate things, mutually isolated and independent, and governed by distinct laws of motion. Therefore, even though originally they are internally united, they become decisively distanced from each other.  Furthermore, Marx discussed each of the laws that govern production and consumption (market). Under capitalistic production relations, production is expanded through anarchical, and accelerated development. On the other hand, consumption, or in capitalistic terms the market, cannot expand in proportion to productive power and production, but is limited under capitalistic production relations (i.e. relations underpinned by the exploitation of labor). Letfs now look more closely at this phenomenon. 


5. gThe Cause of Crisish
   -gLimited Consumptionh and the Development of Unrestricted Productive Power

Marx also emphasized that glimited consumptionh has important meaning for crisis. However, the question is what meaning, and in what sense does it hold important meaning. It is completely meaningless to explain crisis as merely ginsufficient consumptionh and thus propose solving crisis simply through an expansion of consumption, i.e. a wage increase and an alteration of distribution.

Marx repeatedly said that the true cause of crisis is not limited consumption, but capital itself, the limits of capital. The cause and basis of crisis is precisely the limits of capital; crisis is not the result of insufficient consumption. Likewise, the basis of overproduction is not insufficient production, but the glimitsh of capital. The problem is capital itself. What does Marx mean, exactly, by the expression gthe limits of capitalh or gcapital itselfh?

The most characteristic phenomenon of crisis is overproduction. In other words, a situation in which commodities are produced which do not find a demand, so that unsold commodities pile up (in some cases they are burned and in others thrown into the ocean). The superficial view, when faced with this phenomenon (currently represented by the JCP and trade unionists, as well as Keynesianism), says that since consumption is insufficient there must be overproduction, i.e. production that exceeds consumption. Since capitalistic production always keeps the workers wages at the minimum level needed for its existence this view seems to be entirely justified. These are the actual conditions for the prevalence of the theory of underconsumption.

Marx was in fact opposed to this common view and consistently denounced the theory of underconsumption and emphasized that the problem was not simply one of underconsumption, but the original glimitsh existing in capital itself, the essential limits within the capitalistic means of production. According to Marx, the expression goverproductionh conveys a mistaken understanding because it gives the illusory impression that societyfs most essential needs are satisfied. However, as any worker knows, despite even the most urgent needs of the workers being limited, the occurrence of crisis, i.e. overproduction, is not at all rare, but in fact common. In this sense, it is definitely not a question of the demand or the gabsoluteh needs of society. At issue for Marx is gthe capitalistsf profit,h not the needs of society, i.e. the producers. On this same point Marx criticized Ricardo who, following Say, offered up the concept that demand is supply and supply is demand (or production is consumption and consumption is production). For Marx this view completely ignored the particularity of capitalist production. Marx wrote:

gBut the whole process of accumulation in the first place resolves itself into surplus production, which on the one hand corresponds to the natural growth of the population, and on the other hand, forms an inherent basis for the phenomenon which appear during crises. The criterion of this surplus production is capital itself, the scale on which the conditions of production are available and the unlimited desire of the capitalists to enrich themselves and to enlarge their capital, but by no means consumption, which from the outset is inhibited, since the majority of the population, the working people, can only expand their consumption within very narrow limits, whereas the demand for labour, although it grows absolutely, decreases relatively, to the same extent as capitalism develops. Moreover, all equalisations are accidental and although the proportion of capital employed in individual spheres is equalised by a continuous process, the continuity of this process itself equally presupposes the constant disproportion which it has continuously, often violently, to even out.h (MECW Vol. 32 pp. 123-4)

Many things are discussed in this passage. The first point emphasized is that the glimith of capitalistic production, that is, production with the aim of surplus value, is not limited production, but gcapital itself.h Marx positions gthe scale on which the conditions of production are availableh on one hand, and gthe unlimited desire of the capitalists to enrich themselves and to enlarge their capitalh on the other, and emphasizes the contradiction and struggle between them. This is the foundation for the explanation of crisis. The repeated use of this concept in the same expressions shows us that this is fundamental to Marxfs thought. Expressed in slightly different and more general terms, this is the contradiction between the capitalistic relations of production and the rapid, anarchical development and expansion of the productive forces within them.

In this passage Marx also insists that the limits to the production of surplus value are not consumption limited from the outset, which should make it even more clear that the JCPfs theory of underconsumption has nothing to do with Marxism. In terms of consumption, under capitalistic production consumption is limited gfrom the outseth -- the exploitation of the working masses by capital is the condition which precedes their labor and existence. Removing this condition leads to a circular argument which amounts to the same thing as proving the gimpossibility of capitalistic production.h

The impulse to gain wealth and the impulse of capitalization are definitely not the same thing. The impulse to save is not particular to the capitalist, but can be seen in ruling classes preceding the capitalists. The essential characteristic of capitalists is not only their impulse for surplus value, but the impulse for capitalization, i.e. to accumulate capital and expand reproduction. This objective is not merely to expand consumption or accumulate wealth, but to reinvest capital, exploit labor on a greater scale, and obtain ever larger profits. Moreover, this inevitably includes, or is internally connected to, a lowering in the value of commodities through general competition and the increase in productive power, the ruin of many capitalists, and the concentration of capital, an increase in the organic composition of capital, and a trend towards decreased profit ratios.

Letfs look at a few representative passages:

gAssuming the necessary means of production, i.e. a sufficient accumulation of capital, the creation of surplus-value faces no other barrier than the working population, if the rate of surplus-value, i.e. the level of exploitation of labour, is given; and no other barrier than this level of exploitation, if the working population is given. And the capitalist production process essentially consists of this production of surplus-value, represented in the surplus product or the aliquot portion of commodities produced in which unpaid labour is objectified. It should never be forgotten that the production of this surplus-value -- and the transformation of a portion of it back into capital, or accumulation, forms an integral part of surplus-value production -- is the immediate purpose and the determining motive of capitalist production. Capitalist production, therefore, should never be depicted as something that it is not, i.e. as production whose immediate purpose is consumption, or the production of the means of enjoyment for the capitalist. This would be to ignore completely its specific character, as this is expressed in its basic inner pattern.

gIt is the extraction of this surplus-value that forms the immediate process of production, and this faces no other barriers than those just mentioned. As soon as the amount of surplus labour it has proved possible to extort has been objectified in commodities, the surplus-value has been produced. But this production of surplus-value is only the first act in the capitalist production process, and its completion only brings to an end the immediate production process itself. Capital has absorbed a given amount of unpaid labour. With the development of this process as expressed in the fall in the profit rate, the mass of surplus-value thus produced swells to monstrous proportions. Now comes the second act in the process. The total mass of commodities, the total product, must be sold, both that portion which replaces constant and variable capital and that which represents surplus value. If this does not happen, or happens only partly, or only at prices that are less than the price of production, then although the worker is certainly exploited, his exploitation is not realized as such for the capitalist and may even not involve any realization of the surplus-value extracted, or only a partial realization; indeed, it may even mean a partial or complete loss of his capital. The conditions for immediate exploitation and for the realization of that exploitation are not identical. Not only are they separate in time and space, they are also separate in theory. The former is restricted only by the societyfs productive forces, the latter by the proportionality between the different branches of production and by the societyfs power of consumption. And this is determined neither by the absolute power of production nor by the absolute power of consumption but rather by the power of consumption within a given framework of antagonistic conditions of distribution, which reduce the consumption of the vast majority of society to a minimum level, only capable of varying within more or less narrow limits. It is further restricted by the drive for accumulation, the drive to expand capital and produce surplus-value on a larger scale. This is the law governing capitalist production, arising from the constant revolutions in methods of production themselves, from the devaluation of the existing capital which is always associated with this, and from the general competitive struggle and the need to improve production and extend its scale, merely as a means of self-preservation, and on pain of going under. The market, therefore, must be continually extended, so that its relationships and the conditions governing them assume ever more the form of a natural law independent of the producers and becomes ever more uncontrollable. The internal contradiction seeks resolution by extending the external field of production. But the more productivity develops, the more it comes into conflict with the narrow basis on which the relations of consumption rest. It is in no way a contraction, on this contradictory basis, that excess capital coexists with a growing surplus value; for although the mass of surplus-value produced would rise if these were brought together, yet this would equally heighten the contradiction between the conditions in which this surplus-value was produced and the conditions in which it was realized.h (Capital Vol. 3 pp. 352-3)

gIn short, all the objections raised against the obvious phenomena of overproduction (phenomena that remain quite impervious to these objections) amount to saying that the barriers to capitalist production are not barriers to production in general and are therefore also not barriers to this specific, capitalist mode of production. But the contradiction in this capitalist mode of production consists precisely in its tendency towards the absolute development of productive forces that come into continuous conflict with the specific conditions of production in which capital moves, and can alone move.

gIt is not that too many means of subsistence are produced in relation to the existing population. On the contrary. Too little is produced to satisfy the mass of the population in an adequate and humane way.

gNor are too many means of production produced to employ the potential working population. On the contrary. What is produced is firstly too great a section of the population which is in fact incapable of work, which owing to its situation is dependent on the exploitation of the labour of others or on kinds of work that can only count as such within a miserable mode of production. Secondly, not enough means of production are produced to allow the whole potential population to work under the most productive conditions, so that their absolute labour-time is curtailed by the mass and effectiveness of the constant capital applied during this labour time.

gPeriodically, however, too much is produced in the way of means of labour and means of subsistence, too much to function as means for exploiting the workers at a given rate of profit. Too many commodities are produced for the value contained in them, and the surplus-value included in this value, to be realized under the conditions of distribution given by capitalist production, and to be transformed back into new capital, i.e. it is impossible to accomplish this process without ever-recurrent explosions.

gIt is not that too much wealth is produced. But from time to time, too much wealth is produced in its capitalist, antagonistic forms.h (Ibid. pp. 366-7)

gOverproduction is specifically conditioned by the general law of the production of capital: to produce to the limit set by the productive forces (that is to say, to exploit the maximum amount of labour with the given amount of capital), without any consideration for the actual limits of the market or the needs backed by the ability to pay; and this is carried out through continuous expansion of reproduction and accumulation, and therefore constant reconversion of revenue into capital, while on the other hand, the mass of the producers remain tied to the average level of needs, and must remain tied to it according to the nature of capitalist production.h (MECW vol. 32 pp. 163-4) 

gThe ultimate reason for all real crises always remains the poverty and restricted consumption of the masses, in the face of the drive of capitalist production to develop the productive forces as if only the absolute consumption capacity of society set limit to them.h (Capital Vol. 3, Ch. 30)

As is clear from this last passage, for Marx it was not simply the limits of consumption in itself that was considered the cause of crisis, but rather at issue was the limited consumption of the masses in contrast to the impulse to develop productive power as if the only limit were societyfs gabsolute consumption capacity.h The consumption of the people is limited by the capitalistic mode of production, and thus also by its mode of distribution. In capitalistic development, this consumption ultimately is restricted and explodes as crisis.

gTo express this contraction in the most general terms, it consists in the fact that the capitalist mode of production tends towards an absolute development of the productive forces irrespective of value and the surplus-value it contains, and even irrespective of the social relations within which the capitalist production takes place; while on the other hand its purpose is to maintain the existing capital value and to valorize it to the utmost extent possible (i.e. an ever accelerated increase in this value). In its specific character it is directed towards using the existing capital as a means for the greatest possible valorization of this value. The methods through which it attains this end involve a decline in the profit rate, the devaluation of the existing capital and the development of the productive forces of labour at the cost of the productive forces already produced.

gThe true barrier to capitalist production is capital itself. It is that capital and its self-valorization appear as the starting and finishing point, as the motive and purpose of production; production is production only for capital, and not the reverse, i.e. the means of production are not simply means for a steadily expanding pattern of life for the society of the producers. The barriers within which the maintenance and valorization of the capital-value has necessarily to move -- and this in turn depends on the dispossession and impoverishment of the great mass of the producers -- therefore come constantly into contradiction with the methods of production that capital must apply to its purpose and which set its course towards an unlimited expansion of production, to production as an end in itself, to an unrestricted development of the social productive powers of labour. The means -- the unrestricted development of the forces of social production -- comes into persistent conflict with the restricted end, the valorization of the existing capital. If the capitalist mode of production is therefore a historical means for the developing the material powers of production and for creating a corresponding world market, it is at the same time the constant contradiction between this historical task and the social relations of production corresponding to it.h (Capital Vol. 3, pp. 358-9)

In capitalist society, the market does not create production, production creates the market -- no matter how illogical this appears, it is nonetheless profoundly true for capitalistic production. In other words, production and the market are definitely not in agreement, and usually production exceeds the market. The market does not expand in proportion to production, or does not develop or expand as rapidly as production. This is a contradiction, but an inescapable contradiction under capitalism. Under capitalism production exceeding consumption and the market and supply exceeding demand appear as one inevitable law.

According to Marx, production usually expands rapidly. This is because, first of all, the capital invested in production always increases (capital accumulation and the transformation of capital into surplus value is the nature of capital); and secondly, through capital becoming increasingly productive. Hence, production increases rapidly, but the market does not, and cannot, expand to meet this. This does not mean that surplus value, i.e. the value exploited from the workers, is not realized (or gconsumedh), but the failure of the expansion of consumption to keep pace with the expansion of production is one contradiction which at a certain stage necessitates a forced readjustment. If a certain stage of disequilibrium is reached, a violent retraction must occur.

It is absurd to ask the question why this takes a violent form under capitalistic production, and whether this is indeed necessary. In a society in which there is anarchy in production and the various internally united moments, such as value and use value, production and consumption (market), supply and demand, value and its realization, or productive capital and money capital, etc., are externally independent and move and develop according to their own particular laws; that is, in a society penetrated by this sort of disequilibrium, a general crisis is the only means for a readjustment to achieve equilibrium.

Hasnft the bourgeoisie always stressed that things can be safely left to the movement of the gmarket economyh and advocated its usefulness (the usefulness of its anarchistic movement)? In that case, isnft crisis also one of the gautomatich harmonizing effects of the market economy? If they are going to praise the splendid movement of the market, they would also have to accept crisis to be consistent. It is self-contradictory to praise the harmonization and adjustment function of the market, but be frightened by crisis which is the sharpest and most decisive manifestation of this function. If one accepts the market, one must also accept crisis; if one applauds the market, one must also applaud crisis -- because they are both fundamentally the same, and are both the essence of the same capitalistic mode of production. Apart from crisis, there is no other way that equilibrium can be reached in such a thorough form for the sake of capital and its continuation, and those who canft understand this reveal their ignorance. One cannot only credit the market economy for fortunate circumstances without recognizing crisis as a characteristic manifestation of this market economy.

gThe market expands more slowly than production; or in the cycle through which capital passes during its reproduction -- a cycle in which it is not simply reproduced but reproduced on an extended scale, in which it describes not a circle but a spiral -- there comes a moment at which the market manifests itself as too narrow for production. This occurs at the end of the cycle. But it merely means: the market is glutted. Overproduction is manifest. If the expansion of the market had kept pace with the expansion of production there would be no glut in the market, no overproduction. However, the mere admission that the market must expand with production, is, on the other hand, again an admission of the possibility of overproduction, for the market is limited externally in the geographical sense, the internal market is limited as compared with a market that is both internal and external, the latter in turn is limited as compared with the world market, which however is, in turn, limited at each moment of time, [though] in itself capable of expansion. The admission that the market must expand if there is to be no overproduction, is therefore also an admission that there can be overproduction. For it is then possible -- since market and production are two independent factors -- that the expansion of one does not correspond with the expansion of the other; that the limits of the market are not extended rapidly enough for production, or that new markets -- new extensions of the market -- may be rapidly outpaced by production, so that the expanded market becomes just as much a barrier as the narrower market was formerly.h (MECW Vol. 32, pp. 153-4)

According to Marxfs view, production and consumption (market) are distinct from each other, and under capitalism develop and move in a mutually independent and autonomous manner. Certainly both are united and internally connected, but one character of capitalism is that because they are also inescapably mutually independent and in opposition, at a certain stage this contradiction must explode as a crisis. Say, Mill and Ricardo said that production and consumption are simply identical; that production is consumption, and consumption is production (or sales are purchases, and supply is demand). However, the underconsumption theorists as well simply juxtapose production and consumption in the same manner as the equilibrium theorists. They are more or less the same as the equilibrium theorists, since their theory is based on an incorrect understanding (surplus value cannot be realized, etc.) and offers a simplistic account of disequilibrium between production and consumption (market), thus failing to understand the real contradiction within capitalistic production. They understand the contradictions of capitalism in an extremely narrow way. @


6. Crisis and the Fate of the Capitalist Mode of Production

Crisis is the essence of capitalism, and thus its evaluation is at the same time an evaluation of capitalism. It is nonsense to say that capitalism is good and only crisis is bad (e.g. capitalism would be an ideal society if crisis were eliminated). Crisis is the concentrated expression of the contradictions of capitalism which explode in a visible form.

Marx emphasized that crisis revealed the inevitable limits of capitalism and the inevitable limits of this mode of production, which must be transformed into socialism. This conception is precisely the same as the materialist conception of history. For Marx, the recognition of the essential content and limitations of capitalism in itself elucidates the nature of crisis. In this sense, the viewpoint that gthere is no systematic theory of crisis within Marxismh or that gMarx was unwilling to construct a theory of crisish is mistaken.

gBeyond a certain point, the development of the productive forces becomes a barrier to capital, and consequently the relation of capital becomes a barrier to the development of the productive forces of labour. Once this point has been reached, capital, i.e. wage labour, enters into the same relation to the development of social wealth and the productive forces as the guild system, serfdom and slavery did, and is, as a fetter, necessarily cast off. The last form of servility assumed by human activity, that of wage labour on the one hand and of capital on the other, is thereby shed, and this shedding is itself the result of the mode of production corresponding to capital. It is precisely the production process of capital that gives rise to the material and spiritual conditions for the negation of wage labour and capital, which are themselves the negation of earlier forms of unfree social production.h (Grundrisse in MECW Vol. 29, pp. 133-4)

Marx said that each of the essential aspects of capitalism was represented in the theories and thought of Ricardo and Sismondi. Ricardo represents the gpositiveh side of capitalism by disregarding the limits of demand, consumption and the market and how these limits impact the development of the productive forces, and how this trend itself prepares the material conditions for socialism, while Sismondi, for his part, theoretically represents the gnegativeh side of capitalism and its limits, such as the explosions of crisis. According to Marx, in the opposition between these two representative theories, the essence of capitalism, and hence the essence of crisis, is revealed.

gThe universality towards which it (capital) irresistibly strives encounters barriers in its own nature, which will, at a certain stage of its development, allow it to be recognized as being itself the greatest barrier to this tendency, and hence will drive towards its own suspension.

gThose economists who, like Ricardo, conceived production as directly identical with the self-realization of capital -- and hence were heedless of the barriers to consumption or of the existing barriers of circulation itself, to the extent that it must represent counter-values at all points, having in view only the development of the forces of production and the growth of the industrial population -- supply without regard to demand -- have therefore grasped the positive essence of capital more correctly and more deeply that those who, like Sismondi, emphasized the barriers of consumption and of the available circle of counter-values, although the latter has better grasped the limited nature of production based on capital, its negative one-sidednesscSismondi, by contrast, emphasizes not only the encounter with the barriers, but their creation by capital itself, and has a vague intuition that they must lead to its breakdown. He therefore wants to put up barriers to production, from the outside, through custom, law, etc., which of course, as merely external and artificial barriers, would necessarily be demolished by capital. On the other side, Ricardo and his entire school never understood the really modern crises, in which this contradiction of capital discharges itself in great thunderstorms which increasingly threaten it as the foundation of society and of production itself.h (Grundrisse pp. 410-1)

gSismondi is profoundly conscious of the contradictions in capitalist production; he is aware that, on the one hand, its forms -- its production relations -- stimulate unrestrained development of the productive power and of wealth; and that, on the other hand, these relations are conditional, that their contradictions of use value and exchange value, commodity and money, purchase and sale, production and consumption, capital and wage labour, etc., assume ever greater dimensions as productive power develops. He is particularly aware of the fundamental contradiction: on the one hand, unrestricted development of the productive power and increase of wealth which, at the same time, consists of commodities and must be turned into cash; on the other hand, the system is based on the fact that the mass of producers is restricted to the necessaries. Hence, according to Sismondi, crises are not accidental, as Ricardo maintains, but essential outbreaks -- occuring on a large scale and at definite periods -- of the immanent contradictions. He wavers constantly: should the State curb the productive forces to make them adequate to the production relations, or should the productive relations be made adequate to the productive forces? He often retreats into the past, becomes a laudator temporis acti (eulogiser of the past), or he seeks to exorcise the contradictions by a different adjustment of revenue in relation to capital, or of distribution in relation to production, not realising that the relations of distribution are only the relations of production seen sub alia specie (from a different aspect). He forcefully criticises the contradictions of bourgeois production but does not understand them, and consequently does not understand the process whereby they can be resolved. However, at the bottom of his argument is indeed the inkling that new forms of the appropriation of wealth must correspond to productive forces and the material and social conditions for the production of wealth which have developed within captialist society; that the bourgeois forms are only transitory and contradictory forms, in which wealth attains only an antithetical existence and apears everywhere simultaneously as its opposite. It is wealth which always has poverty as its prerequisite and only develops by developing poverty as well.h (MECW, Vol. 32, pp. 247-8)

The significance of these representative passages should be clear. Here it is revealed that the fundamental contradiction of the capitalistic mode of production is the contradiction between productive power and the relations of production, and that crisis is also determined by this.

Finally we need to consider the practical significance of the theories that explain crisis from underconsumption. However, the answer can already be found in the history of capitalism where several varieties of underconsumption theories have appeared and been met with unsparing criticism from the camp of revolutionary Marxists.

Marx criticized the petty bourgeois theorists who hope for gharmonyh between production and consumption through the agreement of gdemand and supplyh in the following way:

gFuit Troja (Troy is no more). This correct proportion between supply and demand, which is beginning once more to be the object of so many wishes, ceased long ago to exist. It has passed into the stage of senility. It was possible only at a time when the means of production were limited, when the movement of exchange took place within very restricted bounds. With the birth of large-scale industry this correct proportion had come to an end, and production inevitably compelled to pass in continuous such cession through vicissitudes of prosperity, depression, crisis, stagnation, renewed prosperity, and so on.

gThose who, like Sismondi, wish to return to the correct proportion of production, while preserving the present basis of society, are reactionary, since, to be consistent, they must also wish to bring back all the other conditions of industry of former times.

gWhat kept production in correct, or more or less correct, proportions? It was demand that dominated supply, that preceded it. Production followed close on the heels of consumption. Large-scale industry, forced by the very instruments at its disposal to produce on an ever-increasing scale, can no longer wait for demand. Production precedes consumption, supply compels demand.

gIn existing society, in industry based on individual exchange, anarchy of production, which is the source of so much misery, is at the same time the source of all progress.

gThus, one or the other:

gEither you want the true proportions of past centuries with present-day means of production, in which case you are both reactionary and utopian.

gOr you want progress without anarchy: in which case in order to preserve the productive forces, you must abandon individual exchange.h (The Poverty of Philosophy, International Publishers, pp. 61-2)

There is nothing add to this passage, because on a daily basis we can confirm that the JCP have become defenders of the goldh petty bourgeois relations on the one hand, and   have prostituted themselves as bourgeois clerks seeking to reform, not revolutionize, the capitalist relations of production, on the other hand. Instead of choosing Marxfs proposal of gone or the other,h for the time being they mix up the two. Of course their progress (degeneration) into the bourgeois-like liberalism of petty bourgeois gcivic activistsh [jiminshugisha] is inevitable, and this shameless development continues right in front of our eyes.

Lenin exposed the practical meaning of the Narodnik (todayfs JCP) theory in the following way:

gIndeed, if we explain crises by the impossibility of realising products, by the contradiction between production and consumption, we are thereby led to deny reality, the soundness of the path along which capitalism is proceeding; we proclaim this path to be a "false one," and go out in quest of "different paths." In deducing crises from this contradiction we are bound to think that the further it develops the more difficult will be the way out of the contradictioncOn the other hand, if we explain crises by the contradiction between the social character of production and the individual character of appropriation, we thereby recognise that the capitalist road is real and progressive and reject the search for "different paths" as nonsensical romanticism. We thereby recognise that the further this contradiction develops the easier will be the way out of it, and that it is the development of this system which provides the way out.h (A Characterization of Economic Romanticism, Collected Works Vol. 2, p. 173)

At the time of Leninfs criticism, capitalism was beginning to develop in Russia. This was thus a period in which the problem was not one of overcoming the capitalistic mode of production, but what path should be pursued to break free of the feudalistic relations. Consequently, Lenin position was that the progressive meaning of capitalist development had to be recognized. Nonetheless, Lenin correctly described the essential nature of crisis and the meaning it held within capitalist production and resolutely countered petty-bourgeois views.

Finally, letfs examine the relation between crisis and the fate of the workers.

One conspicuous phenomenon which crisis exposes is the surplus in labor power. Companies suddenly notice that they possess too much labor power to be able to increase profits. As a result, they begin severe restructuring and focus their attention on firing workers. They are never short of excuses, because if gexcessh labor power is not reduced capital cannot continue to exist. As long as capital survives, gmoralityh can never exist in this society. Capital doesnft care if workers become homeless or donft have enough to eat. To protect itself, capital will permit anything, whether it be firing workers or indirectly killing them For capital anything that is useful is ggoodh and ethical.

Crisis is the violent re-unification and re-adjustment of various independent moments under capital. For this reason, crisis stems from the nature of capital and is a chance for capital to sweep away the surplus population it is burdened by and rid itself of gexcessh labor power for the sake of production for profit and the achievement of equilibrium. It is natural that labor power is subordinated to production for profit, and in this topsy-turvy society anything else is unthinkable.

Crisis and the high unemployment that accompanies it means that labor power has also become gin excessh and this is an essential side of overproduction and surplus capital. But what is excess labor power? An absolute surplus of labor power is unthinkable, and the concept itself is self-contradictory. Under capitalism, like consumption, this is only a surplus for capital.  Labor power becomes a surplus for capital when it is not possible to obtain surplus value through employing it. The rapid development of the productive power of labor has led to a contraction in labor time. For capital, however, this only appears as the contradiction of surplus labor power and the inability of obtaining surplus value through the employment of workers. It is clear that if labor time were reduced rapidly, there would be no problem of an excess of labor time for production. Under socialistic production the problem would appear in such a simple form, but capitalist society is different. Under capitalism, for example, the reduction in labor time through the development of productive power appears as mass unemployment which prepares the resistance of the workers. Under socialism, the total labor of all the people could be reduced on a large scale, and for the individual this would appear as the rapid reduction in labor time, but in capitalist society the development of productive power leads to the abolishment of a large number of workersf jobs, i.e. the loss of the means of living, and if this progresses to an extreme it prepares a revolution. Outside of a revolution, the possibility of a large reduction in labor time of capital is turned into mass unemployment. In other words, a process which should increase the welfare of the workers becomes a source of their misery  because this upside-down system continues to exist.

@


7. The Stalinistsf Concept of Crisis
   -Mendelsonfs Theory and History of Crisis

If we look back at the history of the theoretical debates, Engelsf expression of the contradiction between gthe social character of production and the private character of appropriationh has frequently been cited to explain crisis (especially among Stalinists). The plausible argument has been spread that crisis should not be explained solely through a theory of gunderconsumptionh or gdisequilibriumh but rather must be defined through an explanation of the fundamental contradictions of the capitalistic mode of production. It is not a question, then, of denying the theory of underconsumption or disequilibrium, but of correctly positing it within an overall theory of crisis. According to this logic, if this is not done, a correct understanding of crisis cannot be reached. Now is the time to completely break with this vulgar theory.  As a result of the spread of this gStalinisth dogma the gMarxisth theory of crisis has grown stale and become a boring and obscure heap of redundancy. Today there is nothing as dried up and unappealing as the gMarxisth theory of crisis, and it is no exaggeration to say that the responsibility for this lies with the Stalinists (JCP) and their dogma.

Of course, it is absolutely correct to say that a theory of underconsumption or disequilibrium by itself is mistaken since it superficially explains the contradictions of the capitalistic mode of production, and is thus utilized by reformists and revisionists to serve their own opportunism. Moreover, it is a correct formulation of the problem to say that crisis must also be explained from the fundamental contradictions in the capitalistic mode of production (as Marx said, crisis is the gconcentrated expression of the contradictions of capitalismh). Nevertheless, we certainly cannot say that the Stalinistsf conception is justified. Conversely, this theory has become a source of confusion

A criticism of Stalin has already been carried out, but there has yet to be a complete discussion of works that were written under the influence of Stalinism such as Lev Abramovich Mendelsonfs representative theory of crisis in his book The Theory and History of Crisis [title translated from Japanese]. In this work, which gmodeled afterh Engels and Lenin, the gfundamental causeh of crisis is found in the contradiction between gthe social nature of production and the private (capitalistic) form of acquisition.h But this Stalinist concept has many twists and turns and it is not easy to find the way out.

gThe total sphere of the relations which provide the conditions for the necessity of crisis develop together with the capitalistic mode of production. Further, they stem from the fundamental contradiction of capitalism, i.e. the contradiction between the social character of production and the private, capitalistic form of appropriation. The social nature of production appears in the fact that every product of labor is created through the collected efforts of many people and satisfies some social need.h (The Theory and History of Crisis p. 44 -- passage translated from Japanese)

The cliched idea above forms governs everything else as the basis of the Stalinist theory of crisis. This central cliche leads to a great number of cliches, one after another.

Is this concept just a different way of expressing the contradiction between the relations of production and productive power? If so, it would mean that he has not totally misunderstood the basis of crisis. If, however, this is something different from the concept of the contradiction between the relations of production and productive power it would likely be a gStalinistich dogma that cannot fundamentally explain crisis clearly or correctly. In the conception above, the gprivate, capitalistic form of appropriationh corresponds to the relations of production, and the gsocial character of productionh corresponds to the productive power. However, it cannot be said that this correspondence is justified. For example, gthe social character of productionh and productive power are different things. Although they have a close relationship to each other, this does not mean that the two are equivalent concepts. The same thing can be said of the concept of the gprivate, capitalistic form of appropriationh and the capitalistic production relations. It is clear that the two concepts are not immediately the same thing. The latter concept forms the basis of the relationship between capital and wage labor, while this is not directly true in the case of the former. Of course, in a sense the former could be said to be the same since it is inseparable from the concept of capital and wage labor.

Moreover, the relations of production exist prior to the relations of gappropriationh which is subordinate to them. The relations of gappropriationh do not precede the relations of capitalistic production as a gcondition.h Could it be said then that grelations of appropriationh is just another way of expressing the relations of private property? If this is the case, we would have to question the necessity or importance of introducing the term gappropriationh instead of gprivate propertyh. Furthermore, the laws of private property are not directly the relation between capital and wage labor. Certainly private property fundamentally determines these class relations, but there are several gmediating factorsh that are necessary -- in reality, and thus in theory -- between private property and the class relation between capital and wage labor.

gThe socialization of labor is inseparably linked to the increase in labor productivity, and the introduction of improved methods and means of production, transportation, and communication.h (Ibid. p. 48)

Of course, this proposition is unquestionable. However, this statement if not simply repetitive, is nothing but a hollow truth.

The Stalinists say that this gsocialization of laborh is not unrelated to the development of productive power, but gconnectedh to it. However, we should not be fooled by the vague expression gconnectedh because this is related to the decisively important question of the basis of capitalist contradictions. Of course, to say that it gis connectedh could mean anything. Certainly the gsocialization of laborh is in fact inseparable from and gconnectedh to the development of productive power. As the socialization of labor develops the productive power of labor also reaches a higher level. We recognize that the two progress in parallel. Nevertheless, they are two separate things; the concept of the gsocialization of laborh cannot be equated with productive power.

Of course, the Stalinists donft declare that these two things are the same, they merely say that they are gconnected.h However, by using this expression, they create the impression that the socialization of labor and productive power are the same concept. This vague concept is thus perfectly suited to the Stalinists, who can use this truthful sounding expression to conceal the reality of capitalism.

Moreover, this gfundamental contradictionh is also not unrelated to class struggle.

gThe fundamental contradiction in capitalism is the contradiction between the social character of production and the private form of acquisition. This is because this contradiction expresses the fundamental characteristics of the capitalistic mode of production, and the split of bourgeois society into confrontational classes, i.e. the split between the bourgeoisie who monopolize the social means of production, and the proletariat who are exploited by the bourgeoisie and only possess their own labor power

gThe contradiction between the social character of production and the private form of appropriation is expressed in the collision between the character of large-scale capitalistic production relations and the capitalistic property form including all the other production relations (? ? H. H.). At times, bourgeois economists recognize this or that contradiction in the capitalist economy, but they always deny or conceal the contradiction between the social character of production and private appropriation. If they were to admit this contradiction, it would mean recognizing that the capitalistic property form of the means of production no longer corresponds to, and collides more and more profoundly and violently with, the character of the productive power, and for this reason historically its fate is sealed, and it will be replaced by the socialistic form of property.

gSince the contradiction between the social character of production and private, capitalistic appropriation is the fundamental contradiction within the capitalistic system of production, and expresses the fundamental characteristics of this system, all of the contradictions of bourgeois society are encompassed within this contradiction. In other words, the contradiction between the social character of production and capitalistic appropriation is revealed and expressed in each of the other contradictions of capitalism. The reciprocal, dialectical relation between the fundamental contradiction of capitalism and the other various contradictions is extremely important. Starting from this reciprocal relation, the fundamental problems of the theory of crisis could be correctly solved for the first time.h (Ibid. pp. 50-1)

What Engels, when characterizing capitalistic production, referred to as the private form of acquisition, was the fact that even though the capitalistic commodity becomes a thoroughly social product in the sense that it is already the product of the workers collaborative labor, the capitalist appears as an individual property owner and as such brings the product to market and sells it; in short, the relations of private property. Engels emphasized that in capitalism the relations of small commodity production had already been superceded, and that individual production had come to an end, but even though production is carried out socially, ownership, as before, is still private and individualistic -- it was here that Engels saw a contradiction. Of course this is clearly a contradiction, but it cannot be simply (or directly) said that this is gthe fundamental contradiction of capitalismh and that crisis can be explained from this contradiction. We cannot understand why one would deny the simple but fundamental and comprehensive concept of the contradiction between the capitalistic relations of production and productive power. What is gained by taking this or that word of Engels -- and the words alone-- and turning it into a dogma? Only the Stalinists stand to gain from such a practice. The JCP and others employ such means, and do nothing but scatter around their dogmas. It should be clear to anyone who has read even a little Marx, that when he explained crisis he emphasized the contradiction and conflict between the limits of capitalistic production (the limits of gcapital itselfh) and the expanding productive power that crashes into these limits.

As petty bourgeois private property is transformed into capitalistic private property (capitalistic property relations), the class conflict between the bourgeoisie and proletariat develops. This is an unquestionable proposition. However, to call this gthe contradiction between the social character of production and capitalistic appropriationh and to say that gwithin this contradictionh the capitalistic class relations gare revealedh (!?) only serves to blur the essential relations of capitalistic production and sow confusion among the workers by drawing them into a chaotic storm of meaningless jargon. This is one of the gsystematich ideologies of the Stalinists which was born out of the system of state capitalist society (the system, mistakenly called socialist, of the USSR and China), in other words, a reactionary gdoctrineh.

What the bourgeoisie refuses to gaccepth is not the dogma of the gthe contradictions between the social character of production and capitalistic appropriation,h but rather the contradiction and conflict between capitalistic production relations and productive power, which is a truly revolutionary theory. Of course, under capitalism gcontradictions between the social character of production and capitalistic appropriationh do exist, but there is no reason to call this the gfundamental contradiction.h Moreover, if one says that this is a gfundamental contradictionh in a sense, but only a different and not necessarily superior way of expressing the contradiction and conflict between the relations of production and productive power, then all of the rationales advanced by the Stalinists appear as a nonsensical repetition that amounts to nothing more than a different manner expression. In other words, gthe contradiction between the social character of production and capitalistic appropriationh expresses the contradiction between the relations of production and the productive power, and has the same meaning, etc. However, even though this is too simplistic, the Stalinists say that the former includes or expresses the later, and dress up their arguments to look plausible, which only serves to reinforce the confused and ambiguous nature of their theory.

gThe contradiction between production and consumption and between the potential of production and the low consumption ability of the masses, is an expression of the contradiction between the social character of production and capitalistic appropriationh. (Ibid. p. 51)

gThe contradiction between the social character of production and capitalistic appropriation is also an expression of the anarchy of the capitalist economyh (Ibid. p. 52)

gEven societies of simple commodity production were characterized by a elack of planning,f but under conditions of capitalism, based on the contradiction between the social character of production and the capitalistic form of appropriation, the anarchy of production begins to take a destructive form in the entire course of reproduction.h (Ibid)

Furthermore, according to Mendelson, this is gconditioned by a series of factors,h and these gconditionsh are, first of all, gthe enormous socialization of labor,h secondly, ga constant imbalance,h thirdly, gthe conflict between classes and the contradiction between production and consumption, which is one of its manifestationsh and, finally, increasingly severe, and destructive gcompetition.h

It is extremely difficult to understand clearly what the author is trying to say here, but it is immediately clear to us that this is nothing but a bunch of jargon. He continues in the following way:

gThe contradictions between the social character of production and capitalistic appropriation appears clearly in the gantagonism between the organization of production in the individual workshop and the anarchy of production in society in general.h (Ibid. p. 55)

gThe contradictions between the social character of production and capitalistic appropriation is also revealed in the form of the contradiction between the conditions for the production of surplus value and the conditions of its realization.h (Ibid. p. 56)

gOf the many forms in which the contradiction between the social character of production and capitalistic appropriation is revealed, we have only discussed those which are particularly essential for explaining the inevitability of crisis. Of these, the most important are the confrontation between the proletariat and the bourgeoisie and the anarchy in production.h (Ibid.)

gThe contradiction between the social character of production and capitalistic appropriation is the basis and inescapable cause of crisis. This is because this contradiction is the synthesis of all the contradictions of bourgeois society, and manifests itself in each particular contradiction. Each contradiction (i.e. the anarchy of production, the contradiction between production and consumption, the contradiction between the conditions for the production of surplus value and the conditions for realizing this surplus value, etc.), as the manifestation of this fundamental contradiction of capitalism, can become the cause of crisis.h (Ibid. p. 57)

Mendelson seems to be saying that the contradiction between the social character of production and capitalistic appropriation is the basis of crisis, but on the other hand when this fundamental contradiction is manifested as the contradiction between production and consumption this in tern becomes the cause of crisis. However, this is simply the repetition of the same thing, and is akin to saying nothing at all. This is the argument that the fundamental contradiction is the cause of crisis, but is only the cause of crisis when it appears as the contradiction between production and consumption, and would not be the cause if it didnft appear as such. He says that the fundamental contradiction between production and consumption is not inevitable, but rather that it sometimes manifests itself and sometimes does not. In place of the contradictions of capitalistic production he substitutes some arbitrary or random relations. This line of reasoning is nothing more than sophistry and nonsense.

Enough already! We can already confirm that Stalinism has done nothing but bring confusion and chaos to the workers through its flood of confusing expressions and deceitful theory. The theory of the Stalinists is, generally speaking, dogma and the distortion and revision of Marxism, with their theory of crisis certainly no exception to this. Since the theory of crisis deals with the most fundamental contradictions of capitalism, it is probably inevitable that the Stalinistsh theory of crisis would be total nonsense and degenerate to the point of being nothing but thoroughly reactionary cliches. Based on this theory of capitalism and crisis it is impossible to organize the rebellion of the working class against capitalism. It was certainly no accident that the Stalinists stood idly by and allowed the best opportunity for world revolution to slip away during the Second World War -- as well as the best opportunity for revolution in Japan. They lacked a theory for the overall rebellion and insurrection against capitalism.

The expression: gthe contradiction between the social character of production and the private character of appropriation,h which was used by Engels and then Lenin as a concept to fundamentally explain crisis, has assumed a life of its own ? in words only -- in the Stalinist movement.

In an essay criticizing Narodnik economists, Lenin exposed Sismondifs theory of crisis in the following way:

gSismondi says: crises are possible, because the manufacturer does not know the demand; they are inevitable, because under capitalist production there can be no balance between production and consumption (i.e., the product cannot be realised). Engels says: crises are possible, because the manufacturer does not know the demand; they are inevitable, but certainly not because the product cannot be realised at all. For it is not true: the product can be realised. Crises are inevitable because the collective character of production comes into conflict with the individual character of appropriation.h (A Characterization of Economic Romanticism, p. 171)

The Stalinists use the concept of the gthe contradiction between the social (collective) character of production and the private (individual) character of appropriationh to explain crisis and smugly gapplyh this everywhere to gcrushh their rivals. It is as if this were a magical charm which only required the Stalinists to declare: gall enemies be gone!h.


8. Modern Capitalism and Crisis

Finally, letfs consider the question of modern capitalism and crisis.

Through the establishment of two financial bills, a huge sum of thirty trillion billion yen is being allotted to come to the aid of financial institutions and capitalistic production in general. The banks have jumped at this money and all say that gif we all receive it everything will be fineh. The terrified industrial businesses that have not been able to receive loans have also breathed a sigh of relief and are also celebrating the rise in stock market prices. The money infused through various means by the Bank of Japan to be circulated in the financial markets has swollen to the scale of tens of trillions of yen, and loans issued by the state financial organs have also increased.

However, this massive infusion of state funds is not the characteristic thing about modern capitalism. The characteristic point is that despite being criticized severely by the public just two or three years ago for investing hundreds of billions of yen in public funds when faced with the collapse of the housing loan companies (and solemnly pledging to never again provide public funds to businesses who went bankrupt due to careless management), the government has now openly infused a huge sum of public funds, amounting to ten times the previous sums. The shamelessness, opportunism, and total inconsistency of this action hardly merits mention

This is characteristic in the sense that without the nearly unlimited injection of state capital, which is poured in by means of every form, as if it were water, modern capitalism would not be able to gdirectlyh exist.

In fact, even apart from the new state funds and so on, every year billions of yen in state funds are expended on public enterprises. Expenditures on various forms of gwelfareh are on the scale of billions of yen, and military expenditures have grown increasingly large. The total sum of state money thrown into circulation and trusts to improve the economy, either consciously or by custom, has swelled.

To get a grasp of the scope of this huge sum of money, one need only look at the accumulation of state bonds (debt) that has already reached the sum of hundreds of trillions of yen. The state organs have no prospect (or intention) to repay this debt. Nevertheless, a great amount of new debt is going to be accumulated to add on to this already enormous amount.

The bourgeoisie and politicians are not unaware that there is a huge amount of state debt, and they can vaguely foresee that this debt is a grave problem for the state and society ? i.e., the rule of capital -- that prepares their own collapse. For this very reason they criticize Keynesianism and find it to be the incarnation and root of evil (how very ungrateful of them!). This is also why they are making a fuss over the necessity of gstate restructuringh, i.e. financial reconstruction; and gneo-liberalism,h the antiquated thought of two hundred years ago, takes on a radiance unbefitting its age (of course modern capitalism itself has already reached an gadvanced ageh and is quite senile).

However, they are unable to put an end to state expenditures. This is exactly like some sort of drug addiction. The bourgeoisie realizes that if they continue this will harm their health and progressively ruin their body, but nonetheless they are unable to stop. This is because it is better for them to not know the acute pain that would arise from their chronic disease if they were to give up their medication. They fear crisis, and for this reason they have elected to reduce the pain through state expenditure -- this choice was unavoidable. The arrival of the evil can thus be forestalled, but crisis and unemployment are in fact a direct and imminent problem. The bourgeoisie makes every effort to overcome the dangers it immediately faces and has no room to think about the consequences.

In fact, it wasnft that long ago that oaths were sworn that such a terrible economy could never occur again after the experience of the bubble economy. The bubble economy wreaked damage through the collapse of land and stock prices, the bank recession, and the accumulation of enormous bad debt, which even today continues to have a seriously corrosive effect on the Japanese economy, and is one of the reasons it cannot stay afloat. It could be said that the task of the bourgeoisie these past ten years has been to avoid another bubble economy, and sweep away the aftereffects of the bubble economy as quickly as possible.

However, recent maneuvers teach us that the bourgeoisie cannot stop using inflationary policies, and they have begun to feel that there is no salvation outside of a bubble, or inflationary economy. Clearly they prefer the direction of inflation to that of crisis and recession.

In the mid 1990s, for the first time since the end of the war a national debt appeared, although the finance minister at the time, Fukuda, solemnly swore that this was only temporary, and that when the recession was overcome and the economy revived, tax revenues would be restored and the national debt could be easily repaid. Since that time the bourgeoisie has repeated this same pledge innumerable times. However, not only has the national debt not been repaid, it has grown consistently larger. The national debt would not be repaid even if the economy were to revive, merely the speed of its accumulation would be temporarily slowed somewhat. With the arrival of Prime Minister Tanaka any hope of halting this process was lost.

The nearly ten years since the end of the bubble economy -- especially the experience of the past two or three years -- have made it clear that this bourgeois society cannot cease inflationary policies since this would lead to extraordinary failure. One cannot safely say where this will all end up, but we do know that the bourgeoisie today will continue to rely on inflationary policies. Despite their stated principles, they already have essentially thrown out the slogans of financial reconstruction and reform.

For the modern bourgeois state there is no choice but to pile up inflationary policies and accumulate state debt. Only through these policies can the actual contradictions of overproduction and various imbalances be solved to some extent or postponed. Of course, the contradictions and imbalances are not eliminated by this approach, but in fact become even greater. The policies intended to solve the imbalances in turn create new ones or expand already existing ones, and lead to an uncontrollable situation. This is the trap into which modern capitalism has fallen. Will the bourgeoisie be able to break free, and if they are not able to do so, who exactly (which class or political party representing a class) will be able to show the way out of the impasse?

In one sense, the progression of inflation is a process of stabilizing disequilibrium. Apart from the disequilibrium between production and consumption, the largest as well as most important of these imbalances has been between real capital and money capital. The inflationary policies or the spreading of currency has meant that compared to other forms of capital -- industrial or real capital -- money capital has abnormally swelled. The issue of national bonds itself is an act of self-trust, and is formally completely different from issuing additional paper money. The former simply signifies an expansion of the national debt and national bonds are nothing more than certificates of debt. However, in this form the expansion of state credit (this expanded credit is not necessarily generated from gprivateh natural necessity) causes an enormous accumulation of currency capital relative to productive and industrial capital, i.e., it inevitably leads to disequilibrium. Moreover, it is only through the decrease in the value of currency, i.e. inflation, that the gexcessh money capital can be restored close to its former equilibrium. In this sense, inflation is the gviolenth solution of the causes of abnormally intensified disequilibrium under the managed currency system, and in this sense it carries out the same function as crisis.

Of course, money capital can easily be turned into gcurrencyh and as it appears as increased currency inflation can progress. If money capital is fixed as money capital, no matter how much the Bank of Japan issues bank notes the phenomenon of inflation will not appear. However, we must never forget that in modern capitalism, money capital is currency, and currency is money capital, this is true even apart form the system of controlled currency. However, presently money capital is entangled in circulation and to some extent can become currency, and does become so in some circumstances. In this sense, it can be distinguished from metallic money which is only absorbed into circulation to the extent of its volume needed for circulation.  This part, this gexcessh money capital, can easily be transformed into currency, and therefore it is clear that it can become one of the causes of inflation. Under the current system, the excess of money capital means that inflation penetrates as one necessity. This is an action or movement of capitalism to gain a new equilibrium by means of reducing gexcess.h This gexcessh money capital must be reduced because the foundation and basis of the capitalist mode of production is industrial capital, not money capital, and if money capital expands at the expense of industrial capital, this is an indication that the society is becoming increasingly parasitical and declining. Money capital may secure an income for its owner in the form of interest. However, since interest is only income as a part of the profit generated from industrial capital, if industrial capital dos not produce a profit or if interest receipts swell excessively compared to industrial profits, then this can only mean the decline of interest, and therefore money capital. If money capital becomes gexcessiveh to the point that interest exceeds profit, there is a necessity for this society to dissolve this gexcessh money capital (at least to the point where capital can obtain profit and once again resume gsmoothh reproduction) and regain a sound footing. For example, in Germany after the First World War and Japan after the Second World War, there was the outbreak of strong inflation, but in this process gexcessh money capital was eliminated, and capital was able to begin to reproduce and reaccumulate upon a new basis and equilibrium in order to produce prosperity for capitalist society. Of course, however, this was also the process of the accumulation of new contradictions.

Keynes said that one positive role of inflation is that it causes the ruin of the rentier. For the owners of money capital, who comes to occupy a great relative importance and even become a burden on society, and that class that garners enormous wealth from society in the form of interest, inflation is the most severe blow, which plunders them and brings about their ruin. Even if one has a savings of ten billion yen, the arrival of severe inflation can shrink the value of money to one-thousandth of its former value so that this ten billion yen comes to have the value of just ten million yen. And if this value is reduced to just 1/10,000th of its former value, this savings will have shrunk to just a million yen, so that our hypothetical big capitalist slips down to the level of a miserable petty bourgeois. For the class which had lived an elegant, luxurious life on the interest on savings of a 100 million or 1 billion yen, this inflation would in fact spell ruin, and this is why Keynes could smugly speak of the geuthanasia of the rentier.h And this geuthanasiah of the enormous rentier class, which had grown until it posed a problem to society, means that the problem of debt disappears like magic, and this in term lightens the burden of society as a whole and that of industrial capital.

The bourgeois state, which is suffering under enormous debt, would also likely be the greatest beneficiary of the progression of inflation. If we look at the postwar Japanese state, it should be perfectly clear that the state can also be saved by inflation. The postwar Japanese state was able to free itself of the enormous debt that it had accumulated by borrowing from the Japanese people as a whole to fund its war effort. In other words, the state was in fact able to bilk the public, and do this by legal means. This likewise reminds us of the inevitability and significance of the postwar inflation. This postwar inflation was of course a harsh additional exploitation of the workers, and the process of the grealizationh of this exploitation. The war itself was also pursued by placing an enormous gadditionalh burden on the people, for which they were repaid after the war with a rapid worsening of their standard of living and collapse of their livelihood resulting from the severe inflation of the time.

Apart from the nearly ten year long Great Depression that began in 1929 and lasted up to the Second World War, the 20th century has not known a crisis in the true meaning of the word on a global scale. Of course there have been several recessions since the Second World War, and the experience of several periods of economic crisis and difficulties, such as the gdollar shockh and the goil shock,h but these could not be called crisis in the true meaning of the word. In this sense, modern, post-war, monopoly capitalism has not known crisis.

Still, it would be wrong to declare that this means that in the future there will be no explosion of the contradictions of capitalism (crisis). It would be certainly incorrect to make such a statement. In fact, no matter how thoroughly gderegulationh is carried out, or the principles of free competition are allowed to reign supreme so that the merciless glaw of the jungleh penetrates society, there is no guarantee that this will not bring about a crisis in the gclassich sense of the word (i.e. panic). Indeed, the crisis and bankruptcy last year of not only small and medium size businesses, but also large-scale capital shows that crisis is very possible under modern capitalism and this bewildered the bourgeoisie. If the government had not intervened, it is highly possible that the situation would have escalated to a panic. In this sense, it can be said that through the aid of the state modern capitalism is able to temporarily avert a panic.

Even though the role of the state is genormous,h it would be a fantasy to think that the capitalist economy could become free through state policies or gmanagedh according to the wishes of the bourgeoisie. The ability of the state to gmanageh is temporary or partial, only extending to a certain level or depth. Even if it may appear that a crisis or overproduction is eliminated by means of state intervention, this intervention does not get rid of the contradictions and disequilibrium, but rather preserves them in a twisted form and carries them forward, so that ultimately the crisis continues and steadily worsens. In order to reduce this aggravated crisis in turn requires state intervention on an even larger scale, thereby representing a vicious circle that heads in the direction of bankruptcy and a general collapse.

Seen historically, there were times when the gappropriateh intervention of the state was effective. For example, in the age of Marx, the English state implemented mistaken economic policies that aggravated the crisis of 1848-9 on the basis of Ricardofs theory of the volume of currency, but Marx wrote that by just abandoning these mistaken policies gthe crisis was foiled.h The mistaken policy that the state had implemented was to have the distribution of currency gstrictlyh adhere to the circulation of metallic money -- based on the idea that a crisis stemmed from the issuance of an excessive amount of currency and the resultant economic bubble, and thus it was possible to avoid a crisis through the strict management of currency -- and the technique employed was to remove bank notes from circulation in proportion to the gold that was sent overseas. This, however, in fact lead to an outbreak of crisis resulting from withdrawing currency from circulation at the very moment that it was most needed, and this abnormally aggravated an economic crisis. This gexperimenth failed, and just by removing this system, the peak of the crisis was surmounted and it came to an end. This is an example of the influence of a negative action by the state, but it is certainly possible that it is possible to break the momentum of a crisis by freely and intentionally supplying currency.

This is precisely why monopoly capital society moved from the system of metallic money to a system of controlled currency, i.e. a system in which bank notes are the currency.

If bank notes are covered by metallic money (i.e., if the conversion of bank notes for gold is ensured), then the issuance of bank notes (currency) clearly has a limit. This is not to say that the number of bank notes issued cannot be increased, but if there is a simultaneous demand for the conversion of currency to gold, the central bank will be faced with immediate collapse. Therefore, in order for currency to be issued more freely, the conversion of currency to gold was suspended and then banned. Indeed, it was in the age of monopoly capital, with the intensification of capitalistic contradictions, that the conversion of currency to gold was halted, and indeed had to be halted. Even today the gold system in which currency was convertible has not been gresurrected.h

Certainly inflation is, on the one hand, the extreme development of disequilibrium, but on the other hand this is the process whereby the great amount of disequilibrium that has been inevitably accumulated and developed by the capitalist mode of production is reduced, so that this is both the explosion of contradictions and at the same time the process of the gviolenth resolution of these contradictions and a process of attaining equilibrium, and in this sense inflation had the identical social function as crisis. The rapid development of inflation is indeed a crisis, and therefore it is completely wrong in this sense to say that modern capitalism has eliminated crisis. Of course not only inflation, but war as well is the same, since it is clear that war is a waste of an enormous amount of capital. It was only by means of a large-scale, world war that the overproduction that was manifested with the Great Depression could be finally eliminated, and war was able to bring about the gsmoothh reproduction and expanded reproduction, that is, the resumption of the accumulation process of capital. In this sense, war can also be said to be crisis, with the same movement as crisis -- that is, it plays the a social role that is intrinsically necessary to capitalism. In capitalist society even war (and the bigger one the war the better) has a certain geconomich role to play (an effective and meaningful role!) and a necessity. As the possibility to evade or crush an economic crisis becomes smaller, the social and economic pressure (desire) for a gsolutionh in the form of inflation or war grows stronger and the likelihood of its realization increases. This is the reality of the society in which we live, the reality of the society of monopoly capital.



171-0022,Okiyama Bldg.
1-17-11 Minami-Ikebukuro Toshima-ku Tokyo Japan
tel/fax 03 (3971) 0622

E-mal to WPLL

TOP