Lenin's gOwn Wordsh(Part Five: Theories of the State, Nation and War)
15. The Theory of the State
What is the Essence of the State?
gIf we abstract ourselves from the so-called religious teachings, subtleties,
philosophical arguments and the various opinions advanced by bourgeois
scholars, if we abstract ourselves from these and try to get at the real
essence of the matter, we shall find that the state really does amount
to such an apparatus of rule separated out from human society. When there
appears such a special group of men who are occupied with ruling and nothing
else, and who in order to rule need a special apparatus of coercion and
of subjugating the will of others by force -- prisons, special detachments
of men, armies, etc. -- then there appears the state.h (gThe State,h
Marx, Engels, Marxism, Foreign Languages Publishing House, p. 7)
What is the essence -- not this or that particular quality -- of the state that we are aware
of in everyday life and told to gresolutely defendh? Lenin responds that
this is a special apparatus of coercion that arises from the need to rule
and govern a class-divided society. This general essence of the state has
remained unchanged through the system of slavery and serfdom right up to
the system of capitalism. The division of society into classes means that,
on the one hand, there is a group of people who govern and exploit others,
while on the other hand there are those who are governed and exploited.
In order to compel others to work and continuously appropriate their surplus
labor, it is necessary to have some sort of coercive apparatus -- and thus
the state is formed.
The ruling class, however, does not necessarily present the state as an
ruling-class apparatus, but rather presents it as a community or as an organ that preserves the common interests of both the rulers
and the ruled. Even today there are theories that speak of the neutrality
of the state. The basis for the appearance of such fantasies is that the
ruling class finds that such views serve a certain social function in terms
of maintaining and expanding their own interests. In a period of crisis,
however, it becomes starkly apparent that the state is an apparatus of
force and that it is an illusion to speak of it as a community.
These days there has been a spate of criticism of Leninfs theory of the
state, as seen in the case of the theories of the Structural Reformists.
One scholar has proposed that the present-day state has a dual structure.
According to this view, in addition to the gstate as superstructureh
(Leninfs state as apparatus of force), there is a gstate as substructure,h
and this state as geconomic baseh will also exist under socialism since
it is a gnon-political state.h If one negates the class nature of the
state as economic base, the rest is easy. The only thing necessary would
be to place this gstate as substructureh under democratic control, which
would then invariably lead to the appearance of socialism. The general
characteristic of all such views of the state is an extreme illusion regarding
the gpublic natureh of what is in fact an organ of the ruling class.
Criticism of the Democratic State
gYou say your state is free, whereas in reality, as long as there is private
property, your state, even if it is a democratic republic, is nothing but
a machine used by the capitalists to suppress the workers, and the freer
the state, the more clearly is this expressed. Examples of this are Switzerland
in Europe and the United States in the Americas. Nowhere does capital rule
so cynically and ruthlessly, and nowhere is this so clearly apparent, as
in these countries, although they are democratic republics, no matter how
finely they are painted and not withstanding all the talk about labour
democracy and the equality of all citizens... and nowhere is this suppression
of the working-class movement accompanied by such ruthless severity as
in Switzerland and America, and nowhere does the influence of capital in
parliament manifest itself as powerfully as in these countries. The power
of capital is everything, the stock exchange is everything, while parliament
and elections are marionettes, puppets.h (gThe State,h Foreign Languages
Press, p. 23)
In a democratic state -- present-day Japan being one of its forms -- the
rule of capital is single-handed and appears clearly and gpurely,h since
the state is no longer a coalition that includes feudalistic power. For
this reason, the democratic republic, in one aspect, is historically progressive
and more advantageous than the old feudal absolutist state in terms of
the advancing of the proletariatfs class struggles. On the other hand,
however, this is the direct, gironcladh rule of capital. Whereas in the
past, in the case of the English state for example, the proletariat was
able to obtain some advantage for itself when the state was an organ of
both the landowners and the bourgeoisie and there was a struggle between
the two classes (such as when the landowning class, in retaliation against
the bourgeoisie for the repeal of the Corn Laws, supported legislation
to protect the working conditions of the proletariat). In a democratic
republican state, however, the power of capital is almighty and the parliament
and elections are nothing but its marionettes. The bourgeoisie carries
out its state activities outside of the parliament and behind the scenes
through the state apparatus.
For this reason, no illusions can be held toward the democratic republican
state and the parliamentarian system. It is a terrible fantasy to say that
there is diversity within the parliament or that parliament can become
a gtool of the people.h The issue revolves rather around the smashing
of the state apparatus of the bourgeoisie.
It is worth noting that Lenin exposes the democratic republic of Switzerland,
in addition to that of United States. The JCP has held up Switzerland as
the example of a gneutral state,h calling it a model for workers in Japan
to aim for, but in fact the Switzerland is a state of the despotic rule
of capital, a bourgeois state that must be clearly rejected by the proletariat.
Bourgeois and Proletarian States
gThe [bourgeois state] cannot be superseded by the proletarian state through the process of ewithering
away,f but as a general rule, only through a violent revolution.h (State and Revolution, International Publishers, p. 21)
Here Lenin is criticizing the Second International opportunists and reformists
who one-dimensionally distorted Marxfs theory of the state so that the
gwithering awayh of the state came to mean that the bourgeois state would
gradually and smoothly wither away without a revolution. Although the expression
gwither awayh was originally meant to refer to a proletarian state, the
opportunists emphasized that the state would gwither away,h in opposition
to the anarchists who advocated the gabolitionh of the state. In other
words, whereas the anarchists called for the immediate abolition of the
state, and the state in general, the opportunists called for the state
in general to whither away.
Of course, both sides were incorrect and this resulted in vacillation within
and damage to the proletarian movement. Since the anarchists negated the
state in general, they consequently rejected the task of organizing a proletarian
state in place of the bourgeois state. The result of the anarchistsf rejection
of the proletarian state was their reluctant tailing after semi-bourgeois
popular front governments (e.g. the experience of in 1936). The opportunists,
for their part, by claiming that the state in general (and therefore the
bourgeois state also) would wither away without a revolution, confused
the meaning of revolution and in the end justified and prettified the bourgeois
state.
Lenin criticized the one-dimensionality of both sides, clearly stating
that the bourgeois state must be gabolishedh by means of proletarian
revolution, and that only the proletarian state, or the gsemi-state,h
would be able to wither away.
On Proletarian Democracy
gProletarian democracy, of which Soviet government is one of the forms,
has brought a development and expansion of democracy hitherto unprecedented
in the world.h (gThe Proletarian Revolution and the Renegade Kautskyh
Foreign Languages Press, p. 25)
In this passage, Lenin clarifies the difference between bourgeois democracy
and proletarian democracy, and discusses the class content of democracy.
Kautsky and others juxtaposed the dictatorship of the Bolshevik government with democracy in general, criticizing the former, while Lenin countered that the Soviet government
was a higher form of democracy, proletarian democracy. He said that as
long as democracy was the state, it would be the rule of one class against
another, and in this sense a gdictatorship.h Even a democratic republic
does not change the fact that it is a gdictatorship of the bourgeoisie.h
Kautsky attempted to conceal this reality by introducing the issue of democracy
in general or gpure democracy.h Proletarian democracy, for its part,
is rule against the bourgeoisie and in this sense a gdictatorship,h but
since this is in fact a state of the masses, it is a hundred or a thousand
times more democratic than a bourgeois state.
Of course, the theory of proletarian democracy discussed here is the abstract
concept and should not be confused with the actual state under Stalin.
In Russia during the era of Stalin, it was the case that not only proletarian
democracy, but even formal democracy (i.e. bourgeois democracy), was lacking
(and this remains the case).
Criticism of the "Democratic Coalition Government"
gThat is why it always happens, under all sorts of ecoalitionf Cabinets
that include esocialists,f that these socialists, even when individuals
among them are perfectly honest, in reality turn out to be either a useless
ornament of or a screen for the bourgeois government, a sort of lightning
conductor to divert the peoplefs indignation from the government, a tool
for the government to deceive the people. This was the case with Louis
Blanc in 1848, and dozens of times in Britain and France, when socialists
participated in Cabinets. This is also the case with the Chernovs and Tseretelis
in 1917. So it has been and so it will be as long as the bourgeois system
exists and as long as the old bourgeois, bureaucratic state apparatus remains
intact.h (gOne of the Fundamental Questions of the Revolution,h Collected Works, Vol. 25 p. 373)
Unlike todayfs pseudo-communists, Lenin emphasized that socialists (and
gcommunistsh) participating in democratic coalition governments are tools
of the ruling class and serve as a veil. The reason for this is that such
governments do not lift a finger to change the old state apparatus. Today,
the actual work of the government is carried out by an enormous army of
bureaucrats, and a reshuffling of ministers or even a change in governments
has little real significance. Since none of the democratic coalition governments
that have included socialists or gcommunistsh abolished this state structure
or this bureaucratic army, they were unable to carry out proletarian policies
and ultimately met with inevitable failure.
Since Lenin wrote these words, opportunism -- that is, opportunism in the
sense of participating in and entering bourgeois states and trying to move
them in some sort of gsocialist directionh instead of striving to smash
the bourgeois state apparatus and establish a proletarian government --
has provided us with a wealth of experience concerning coalition governments.
Democratic coalition governments emerged in many Europe countries following
the First World War, and even the best of them demonstrated their impotence
in terms of being a proletarian revolutionary power (the Sachsen-Thueringen
government in Germany, or to a certain extent the Bela Kun government in
Hungary), while the worst of the social-democratic coalition governments
made every effort to strangle the proletarian revolution (the German Scheidemann,
Noske government).
And there are innumerable cases where a democratic coalition government
has acted as a lightening rod to deflect the anger of the proletarian masses.
The 1918 coalition government in Austria composed of the Austrian Social
Democratic Party and the Christian Social Party (a bourgeois liberal party),
the 1923 coalition government in England made up of the Labor Party and
Liberal Party, the 1924 Kuomintang-CCP coalition government in China, as
well as the democratic collation government in Germany prior to the victory
of the Nazis -- these are all essentially identical examples.
Before and after the Second World War, the main advocates of democratic
coalition governments were the Stalinists, who had changed tactics, abandoning
their theory of gsocial fascismh --according to which social democrats
and fascists are identical in terms of being the agents of the bourgeoisie
-- in favor of the theory of the popular front. There were democratic coalition
governments in France, both in 1935 and after the war, in Spain in 1936,
and in Italy following the war, and in each case these were as a popular
front governments. In France and Italy after the Second World War, Stalinist
gcommunistsh (who are in fact Millerandists) entered bourgeois cabinets,
but this was just like Chernov who gworked as a Ministerh in 1917, in
the sense that they were unable to do anything for the masses and surrendered
openly to the bourgeois government.
In Japan after the Second World War, a coalition government composed of
the Socialist Party and Democratic Party was formed (the Katayama government),
but the complete impotence and lack of direction of this government was
exposed. The innumerable examples of this sort of experience demonstrate
the correctness of the Marxist-Leninist theory of the state, which emphasizes
the fact that a popular front government that seeks to organize a government
on the basis of the bourgeois state structure, rather than smashing this
old state structure, will be unable to wage the struggle for socialism.
Criticism of the "Free People's
State"
gThe efree peoplefs statef was a program demand and a catchword among
the German Social-Democrats in the seventies. This catchword is devoid
of all political content except that it describes the concept of democracy
in a pompous philistine fashion. Insofar as it hinted in a legally permissible
manner at a democratic republic, Engels was prepared to ejustifyf its
use efor a timef from an agitational point of view. But it was an opportunistic
catchword, for it amounted to something more than prettifying bourgeois
democracy, it was also a failure to understand the socialist criticism
of the state in general.h (State and Revolution, pp. 19-20)
gA free peoplefs stateh became a fashionable slogan within the German
Social-Democratic Party near the end of the 19th century. Lenin said that
this slogan was nothing but a petty-bourgeois exaggeration of the concept
of democracy.h Engels, for his part, considered this an empty expression.
The reason for this evaluation was the fact that ultimately this slogan
was a one-dimensional abstraction of bourgeois democracy and amounted to
its prettification. We must point out that this fantasy of a gpeoplefs
stateh is not a question of ancient history. The JCP, for instance, today
is calling for a new democratic revolution, a peoplefs democratic revolution,
against monopoly capital in Japan. We can understand why Mao Tse Tung would
propose such a slogan, even if it is incorrect from the perspective of
Marxism, since in the case of this was an ideological reflection of the
agrarian revolution. In the case of Japan, however, which has already reached
the point of being a highly-developed capitalist state and realized a democratic
republic, this slogan is unacceptable, even from a temporary, agitational
standpoint. If this were to be brought about it would probably amount to
a popular front government. Such governments, however, which arise during
a period of crisis for bourgeois rule, play the objective role of allowing
the bourgeoisie to ride out the crisis by temporarily taking over the reins
of government from the bourgeoisie. There would be no reason why the
slogan of the gpeoplefs state,h which was rejected in the time of Marx,
could be viewed as being correct today.
Centralized Authority and Regional
Autonomy
gThe philistine opportunism of that etrendf lies in the fact that people
forget the narrow limits of so-called emunicipal socialismf (in reality,
municipal capitalism, as the English Social-Democrats properly point out
in their controversies with the Fabians). They forget that so long as the
bourgeoisie rules as a class it cannot allow any encroachment, even from
the emunicipalf point of view, upon the real foundations of its rule;
that if the bourgeoisie allows, tolerates, emunicipal socialism,f it
is because the latter does not touch the foundations of its rule, does
not interfere with the important sources of its wealth, but extends only
to the narrow sphere of local-expenditure, which the bourgeoisie itself
allows the epopulationf to manage. It does not need more than a slight
acquaintance with gmunicipal socialismh in the West to know that any
attempt on the part of socialist municipalities to go a little beyond the
boundaries of their normal, i.e., minor, petty activities, which give no
substantial relief to the workers, any attempt to meddle with capital,
is invariably vetoed in the most emphatic manner by the central authorities
of the bourgeois state.h (gThe Agrarian Program of Social-Democracy in
the First Russian Revolution,h Collected Works Vol. 13, p. 360)
The established gleftwingh parties in Japan told workers that if they
elected gprogressive prefectural governorsh and gprogressive city mayorsh
and created gbright regional governments,h this gdemocratic camph would
be able to truly act in the interests of residents. However, even if a
number of gprogressiveh mayors were to emerge, what they would be able
to accomplish, as Lenin points out, would be extremely limited. Monopoly
capital and the LDP have a grasp on the central power of the state apparatus. And in terms of the regional governments, they are in fact about 80 percent
dependent on the central government.
A policy for the workers that would actually threaten the basis of monopoly
capitalfs interests, not only in words but in deeds, would be obstructed,
prevented and rejected by the central government. Workers must recognize
the narrow limits of regional governments, and think of the fundamental
issues, including the bourgeoisie as a class and its rule, the overall
economic system of capitalism, and the overall state apparatus. It is necessary
to defeat the excessive fantasies held towards local governments by the
established gleftwingh political parties in Japan, who, like the gmunicipalisersh
in Leninfs day, gseek to divert public attention away from the fundamental
questions of the economic system as a whole, and of the state structure
as a whole, to minor questions of local self-government.h (Lenin, Ibid.
p. 359) The bourgeoisie itself tries to make it appear its small expenditures
in the realm of local self-governments is for the sake of the gneeds of
the residentsh and that in this realm all there is class harmony between
the gdemocratich political parties. In this area of local-government
the JCP is able to propose gurgent demandsh (?) -- for example the construction
of a pedestrian bridge -- that even the LDP would agree to. But this only
shows that the JCP has become a petty-bourgeois party that is totally taken
in by the notion of gsocial harmony.h
To know the degree to which gmunicipal socialismh or gmunicipal communismh
(i.e. municipal capitalism) is a reactionary illusion, one need only look
at the policies carried out by Tokyo governor Minobe who sold himself as
a friend of the workers, (See part 6, chapter 18 on united fronts)
<<Before || Lenin Index || Next>>
|