Rosa Luxemburg and the National Problem:
The Similarity of Luxemburgfs Theory
to gAustrian Marxismh
Writen by Hiroyoshi Hayashi (1993)
Translated by Roy West
Contents
- Introduction
- The Abstract Denial of Nationalism
- Are the National Tasks Bourgeois Tasks?
- The Theory of the gNation-Stateh and the Class Interests of the Workers
- The gNational Self-Determinationh of Poland
- Centralized Power and Regional Autonomy
- Luxemburgfs Concept of Nation
- Luxemburg Begins to gSelecth or Screen Nations
- National Cultural Autonomy and National Self-Determination
1. Introduction
Lenin criticized Rosa Luxemburgfs nation theory for being abstract and
not dealing with the problem concretely and historically. This has become
a sort of gaxiomh that has spread throughout the socialist movement.
This is the idea that Luxemburg, from a standpoint of abstract internationalism,
denied national self-determination, which she thought could only have reactionary
meaning because imperialism had broken through national boundaries and
the nation. In this way she is said to have gforgottenh about the nationalism
and imperialism of the great powers and cut herself off from the working
class in the nationally oppressed nations. Of course this is perfectly
true, and this weak point is clearly one essential aspect of Luxemburgfs
theory-and therefore her political standpoint. However, here we are interested
in another aspect of Luxemburgfs theory, which has basically been neglected:
the aspect of her theory that resembles, or caters to, the theory of gnational
cultural autonomy.h This aspect has a close, internal connection to the
standpoint of abstract internationalism that Lenin criticized, but at the
same time has its own independent content that needs to be critically examined.
We are interested in this aspect of her theory because it is essentially
the same tendency that was appeared within our party a year ago in the
form of Sakaifs theories on the nation and the question of Korean residents
in Japan. Luxemburgfs theory of the nation is presented in her essay,
gThe National Question and Autonomy,h which Lenin also quoted from and
criticized in his essay, gOn the Right of Nations to Self-Determination.h
In Luxemburgfs essay, it is not so much her internationalist standpoint,
but her similarity to the gcultural and national autonomyh theories of
the gAustrian Marxistsh that is exhibited-i.e., in a sense she expresses
not internationalism, but a very nationalistic viewpoint. Of course the
details are different, but we can easily confirm that Luxemburgfs dogmatic
standpoint is ultimately similar to the opportunistic standpoint of the
Austrian Marxists. In this sense, Luxemburgfs nation theory is extremely
opportunistic and nationalistic. This is what we intend to demonstrate
in this essay. This will also reconfirm the ridiculousness of the criticism
of Sakai that we are gsimilar to the nationalism theory of Luxemburg and
that the SWP also adopts her standpoint of abstract internationalist.h
In fact, Luxemburgfs nation theory has essentially the same opportunistic
content as Sakaifs theory, and this will become clear as we develop our
criticism here. Therefore, here we will see the nature of Luxemburgfs
theory, and in what sense it is reactionary or nonsensical. [Quotations
are taken from The National Question: Selected Writings by Rosa Luxemburg
(New York: Monthly Review Press, 1976)].
2. The Abstract Denial of Nationalism
Leninfs criticism of Luxemburgfs theory mainly focuses on the first part
of her work. We will begin by looking at this aspect of her theory. Here,
one fundamental defect in her theory was exposed. For example, in the following
passage Luxemburg argues that the slogan or program of gnational self-determinationh
is totally useless for the correct development of workersf daily class
struggles or political activities:
The formula, gthe right of nations to self-determination,h of course
doesnft have such a character at all. It gives no practical guidelines
for the day-to-day politics of the proletariat, not any practical solution
of nationality problems. For example, this formula does not indicate to
the Russian proletariat in what way it should demand a solution of the
Polish national problem, the Finnish question, the Caucasian question,
the Jewish, etc. It offers instead only an unlimited authorization to all
interested gnationsh to settle their national problems in any way they
like. (p. 109)
Of course, Luxemburg is not denying the national oppression of Poles, Caucasians,
or Jews. She was aware that this existed. However, she emphasizes that
this should be opposed not on the basis of some particular right, such
as the gright to self-determination,h but rather: g[t]his duty arises
solely from the general opposition to the class regime and to every form
of social inequality and social domination, in a word, from the basic position
of socialism.h (p. 110) Therefore, she concludes that the gthe formula
of ethe right of nations to self-determination,f is essentially not a
political and problematic guideline in the nationality question, but only
a means of avoiding that question.h (Ibid)
In order to verify her own theory, Luxemburg says that Marx and others,
when approaching the national problem, started not from the abstract formula
of gnational self-determination,h but from the concrete situation. For
example, Marx compared the 14th century revolt of Canton in Switzerland (a province which had particularly
strong autonomy) to the 19th century Magyar movement, and evaluated the former as reactionary, while
gfervently supportingh the latter. For Luxemburg, this different attitude
towards the same struggle for the gright of national self-determinationh
shows that the abstract defense of the right of self-determination has
nothing in common with Marx.
Luxemburg then ridicules national self-determination under capitalism as
a similarly utopian idea as gthe right to workh under capitalism:
Actually, even if as socialists we recognized the immediate right of nations
to independence, the fates of nations would not change an iota because
of this. The grighth of a nation to freedom as well as the grighth
of the worker to economic independence are, under existing social conditions,
only worth as much as the grighth of each man to eat off gold plates,
which, as Nicolaus Chernyshevski wrote, he would be ready to sell at any
moment for a ruble. (pp. 122-3)
Here, Luxemburgfs theoretical defect of being unable to distinguish between
bourgeois liberation and socialist liberation is perfectly clear. She declares
that gnational self-determinationh will make no difference in the fate
of a country. However, bourgeois emancipation is no minor gchangeh for
the people involved?including the working class as one element of the people?and
to deny this only reveals an ignorance of the historical meaning and limitations
of bourgeois emancipation, and an actual abandonment of the task of Marxists
to correctly determine the workers struggles on the basis of a correct
understanding of this. It is not certain what Luxemburg means by gthe
right of the worker to economic independenceh?she also speaks of the gright
of workh?but if this is understood as a socialistic right, it is needless
to say that this cannot be realized within the framework of capitalism.
However, what is the point in comparing gnational self-determinationh
to socialist rights? If it were a question of whether this could be realized
within the framework of capitalism, then gnational self-determinationh
should be compared to other democratic rights rather than socialistic rights.
In that case, the theoretical confusion and utopian nature of her view
that this right cannot in any sense be realized under capitalism would
be clear. Luxemburg writes the following:
Hopes of solving all nationality questions within the capitalist framework
by insuring all nations, races, and ethnic groups the possibility of eself-determinationf
is a complete utopia. (p. 123)
For her, this is different from the demand for the eight-hour day?even
if it is the same in terms of not being immediately realizable?and is rather
a utopia from the viewpoint of gthe trend of historical development of
contemporary societiesh (p. 124) because in the course of history all
of the nationalities are already gextremely mixed.h
According to Luxemburg, the eight-hour workday can be said to be realizable
under capitalist society by means of bourgeois reforms under certain conditions.
However, she says that national self-determination is different, and in
this way it is certainly not a bourgeois right. This can be realized under
socialism, but under capitalism it is totally impossible. Luxemburgfs
opinion was the polar opposite of Lenin, who viewed national self-determination
as one of the bourgeois tasks?i.e. possible under capitalism through bourgeois
reforms. Here is a fundamental difference between the Marxist Lenin and
the utopian, romantic Luxemburg. In the following passage, Luxemburg explains
why national self-determination is impossible:
Today, in each state, ethnic relics bear witness to the upheavals and intermixtures
which characterized the march of historical development in the past. Even
in his time, Marx maintained that these national survivals had no other
function but to serve as bastions of counter-revolution, until they should
be completely swept from the face of the earth by the great hurricane of
revolution or war. (p. 124)
Luxemburg then criticizes Kautskyfs concept of the national state?the
idea that capitalistic development strengthens national consciousness,
and that the national state is the form of the state gbest corresponding
to modern conditions, the form in which it can most easily fulfill its
tasks.h (Kautskyfs Nationality and Internationalism quoted by Luxemburg on page 129.) Luxemburg argues that a gebestf national
state is only an abstraction which can easily be described and defined
theoretically, but which doesnft correspond to reality.h (p. 129) Against
Kautskyfs gbest national formh, Luxemburg posits the general tendency
of development towards ga universal community of civilizationh (why is
this introduced here?) which involves gthe deadly struggle among nationsh
in gthe tendency to create great capitalist states.h (Ibid) The universal
tendency of capitalism, according to Luxemburg, lies within this gdeadly
struggle among nationsh and gtendency to create great capitalist states,h
not in the trend of the right of national self-determination. She thinks
that ultimately, the small nations can ultimately only be gpolitically
impotent,h and that it is gan illusionh to think that they can be gpoliticallyh
independent.
The return of all, or even the majority of the nations which are today
oppressed, to independence would only be possible if the existence of small
states in the era of capitalism had any chances or hopes for the future.
Besides, the big-power economy and politics?a condition of survival for
the capitalist states?turn the politically independent, formally equal,
small European states into mutes on the European stage and more often into
scapegoats. Can one speak with any seriousness of the gself-determinationh
of peoples which are formally independent, such as Montenegrins, Bulgarians,
Rumanians, the Serbs, the Greeks, and, as far as that goes, even the Swiss,
whose very independence is the product of the political struggles and diplomatic
game of the gConcert of Europeh? From this point of view, the idea of
insuring all gnationsh the possibility of self-determination is equivalent
to reverting from Great-Capitalist development to the small medieval states,
far earlier than the fifteenth and sixteenth centuries. (pp. 129-130)
No matter how justified Luxemburgfs view may be?i.e. no matter how true
it might be that small nations, not only in Europe but generally, have
been unable to play a major determining role in world politics, already
only exist in a state of gpolitical impotenceh or in a supporting role,
or are in the wretched situation of being tools of large states that brandish
them about?the question of the rights of smaller, weak states is a separate
issue. That is, she fails to understand the essence and nature of gbourgeois
rights.h The issue of bourgeois rights is not limited to whether it is
beneficial to those employ them or to society in general, and for this
very reason they are bourgeois rights. (Incidentally, this is also why
Marxists do not absolutize or abstractly prettify these grights,h and
ridicule the opportunistic confusion of those Stalinists who fix them in
place as the foundation of their political practice, i.e. Miyamoto Kenji
and Fuwa Tetsuzo.) It is perfectly irrelevant to bourgeois rights whether
the gnational self-determinationh of a small country is in the interest
of that nation and has progressive significance for humankind and history,
or whether it only satisfies the self-conceit of a nation. Lenin accused
Luxemburg of being unable to conceptually understand the question of bourgeois
rights correctly, by confusing it with the question of whether a small
state could truly be economically independent. For Lenin, the question
of national self-determination is a question of political independence
and the freedom of nations to organize a state under their own will, whereas
the question of whether this state could be economically independent belongs
to another dimension of the problem. Luxemburg was unable to understand
this fundamentally important question, and was thus criticized by Lenin
for being gabstract rather than dialectical.h
As a result of this, Luxemburg went so far as to deny the national self-determination
of colonial people, and thus in fact inescapably fell into the position
of actually defending or justifying capitalistic imperialism. The following
passage is characteristic:
Apparent exceptions only confirm on closer analysis the conclusion that
the modern development of capitalism cannot be reconciled with the true
independence of all nationalities.
It is true the problem appears much simpler if, when discussing nationality,
we exclude the question of colonial partitions. Such a technique is often
applied, consciously or unconsciously, by the defenders of the grights
of nationsh; it also corresponds to the position with respect to colonial
politics taken, for example, by Eduard David in the German Social Democracy
or van Kol in the Dutch. This point of view considers colonialism in general
as the expression of the civilizing mission of European peoples, inevitable
even in a socialist regime. This view can be briefly described as the gEuropeanh
application of the philosophical principle of Fichte in the well known
paraphrase of Ludwig Brone: gIch bin ich?was ausser mir ist Levensmittelh [gI am myself?what is outside of me is the means of lifeh]. If only
the European peoples are regarded as nations proper, while colonial peoples
are looked on as gsupply depots,h then we may use the term gnation-stateh
in Europe for countries like France, Denmark, or Italy, and the problem
of nationality can be limited to intra-European dimensions. But in this
case, gthe right of nations to self-determinationh becomes a theory of
the ruling races and betrays clearly its origin in the ideologies of bourgeois
liberalism together with its gEuropeanh cretinism. In the approach of
socialists, such a right must, by the nature of things, have a universal
character. The awareness of this necessity is enough to indicate that the
hope of realizing this grighth on the basis of the existing setup is
a utopia; it is in direct contradiction to the tendency of capitalist development
on which Social Democracy has based its existence. A general attempt to
divide all existing states into national units and to re-tailor them on
the model of national states and statelets is a completely hopeless and
historically speaking, reactionary undertaking. (pp. 133-4)
There are several problems with this argument. First of all, why does Luxemburg
speak of the independence of gall nationsh? The self-determination of
nations is completely different from the gindependence of all of the nationsh
of the world (of course, there is the question here of what the word gnationh
refers to, but even if this were to mean all gracesh the problem would
be the same). Recognizing the gright of self-determinationh of all nations
is completely different from working for their self-determination or saying
that this is always desirable. Luxemburg is unable to consistently understand
this, and thus ends up speaking of gthe self-determination of all nations.h
Moreover, Luxemburg brings up the problem of imperialism and colonies.
Of course, it is perfectly fine to bring up this problem here, but this
does not justify her position. What she is saying here is confused, and
it is not clear why she refers to the problem of imperialism and colonies.
She says that because it is the European bourgeoisie who insist on gnational
self-determination,h it must be nonsense. However, even though the gnational
self-determinationh of the bourgeoisie in the imperialist states is deceptive
and deceitful, this does not mean that the gnational self-determinationh
of the exploited nations is the same thing. Luxemburg is perfectly justified
to notice that the goriginh of the slogan of national self-determination
comes form bourgeois liberalism?at least Rosa Luxemburg is free from the
stupidity of the Communist Party which fails to realize the bourgeois goriginh
of this slogan, and instead raise it as the essence of gscientific socialismh!?but
she denies the fact that this bourgeois slogan has historically progressive
meaning in the colonial areas since they are in a different historical
and social situation and developmental stage than the economically advanced
capitalist countries. The abstract and idealistic standpoint of Luxemburg
is clear. On the basis of her idea that the slogan of gnational self-determinationh
had already become reactionary in Europe, she concludes that it is also
reactionary in the colonial areas.
Since Luxemburg emphasizes that the terrible exploitation of the colonial
states by the imperialist European states, one would think that she would
naturally emphasize the task of natural liberation in these colonies. In
fact, however, she says the opposite. Luxemburg attacks opportunists for
defending the policy of imperialism by calling it a gcivilizing mission,h
but on the other hand, she abstracts the aspect of the inevitable capitalistic
development of the colonial areas from the colonial rule of the imperialist
states, and thus emphasizes that it would be reactionary for the colonies
to separate into gnational units.h In other words, Luxemburgfs position
is not so different from the opportunistic wing of the Social Democratic
Party. Therefore, her criticism of imperialism (and struggle against it)
was inevitably incomplete.
|