Rosa Luxemburg and the National Problem:
The Similarity of Luxemburgfs Theory
to gAustrian Marxismh
Writen by Hiroyoshi Hayashi (1993)
Translated by Roy West
4. The Theory of the gNation-Stateh and the Class Interests of the Workers
Next we will consider the question of the gnation-state.h This is a theoretically
(and therefore practically) important point because the concept of the
nation is inseparably connected to the bourgeois state (and its form).
The essential understanding of the bourgeois state is the basis for the
concept of the gnation.h
Luxemburg shows a particular understanding of the gnation-state,h which
is connected to her theory of the nation. She begins by critically examining
Kautskyfs theory of the gnation-state,h and notes that Kautskyfs theory
of the nation-state consists of the following three moments:
In his article on the struggles of the nationalities and the social-democratic
program in Austria, published over ten years ago, Kautsky enumerates three
factors, which, according to him, make up the groots of the modern national
idea,h as found in the rise of the modern state in all of Europe. These
factors are: the desire of the bourgeoisie to assure for itself an internal
or domestic market for its own commodity production; second, the desire
for political freedom?democracy; and finally, expansion of the national
literature and culture to the populace. (p. 159)
Luxemburg does not agree with Kautskyfs concept. However, the focus of
her criticism is not Kautskyfs eclecticism of confusing economic and historical
elements with the ideational elements. Indeed, she fails to notice that
Kautsky understands the nation-state as fundamentally the gnationalh
state [minzoku kokka]. According to Luxemburg, the nation-state is not a gnationalh state,
but rather its essential characteristic is that the bourgeoisie of a certain
nation govern or oppress several?or many?of the other nations which surround
it. Therefore, this state essentially is not a gnationalh state, and
she concludes that the bourgeois state can not be a gnationalh state.
This is said to be true both historically, as well as theoretically. The
gtheoryh she presents in order to justify her dogma is the following?first,
Luxemburg asserts that the nation-state was formed differently from what
Kautsky claims.
However, it would be wrong to take Kautskyfs formulation literally; we
cannot assume that the material foundation of modern national movements
is only the vaguely understood appetite of the industrial bourgeoisie for
a gnativeh market and its commodities. (p. 162)
Luxemburg says that Kautskyfs material foundation of national movements
is incorrect or incomplete, and thus one naturally expects her to propose
an alternative gmaterial basis.h Instead she offers the following:
Moreover, a capitalistic bourgeoisie needs many other conditions for its
proper development: a strong military, as a guarantee of the inviolability
of this gfatherland,h as well as a tool to clear a path for itself in
the world market; furthermore, it needs a suitable customs policy, suitable
forms of administration in regard to communications, jurisdiction, school
systems, and financial policy. The bourgeoisie needs for its normal existence
not only strictly economic conditions for production, but also, in equal
measure, political conditions for its class rule. (p. 162)
This explanation, however, is complete nonsense, because what Luxemburg
proposes here does not even come close to being the material foundation
of the nation-state. These are rather political elements that make up the
gsuperstructureh of the state?i.e. not the cause of the state, but simply
its outcome. Needless to say, to understand the state from this aspect
represents the typically petty bourgeois tendency of gpoliticism.h Luxemburg
claims that Kautskyfs concept of the state is incorrect, and that the
theory of its material basis is strange, but what she offers in its place
does not amount to a refutation of Kautsky. This is because Luxemburg cannot
offer an alternative gmaterial foundationh to that of Kautsky. No one
would object to the idea that the class state has need of an apparatus
of violence. However, it is completely mistaken to present this violent
apparatus as the gmaterial foundationh of the state, in the place of
the material foundation of commodity=capitalistic production. We have to
firmly oppose such a frivolous distortion of Marxism.
But it soon becomes clear why Luxemburg offers such a nonsensical idea.
She does not accept Kautskyfs concept of the nation-state, and instead
offers her own concept:
From all this it follows that the specific form of national aspirations,
the true class interests of the bourgeoisie, is state independence. The nation-state is also simultaneously that indispensable historical
form in which the bourgeoisie passes over from the national defense to
an offensive position, from protection and concentration of its own nationality
to political conquest and domination over other nationalities. (p. 162)
The lack of necessity in Luxemburgfs theoretical development is extremely
tiresome. We have no great objection to the idea that the class interests
of the bourgeoisie seek state independence. However, it is not clear at
all why this concept is connected to the earlier concept that the state
requires an apparatus of force. Here the state is explained solely from
political necessity, and this political necessity is said to be determined
by gnational ruleh rather than from class rule (i.e. the violent apparatus
to rule the workers, and make their suppression and exploitation possible).
This is the gparticularityh of Luxemburgfs theory of the state.
According to Luxemburgfs view, the formation of the nation-state also
marks the beginning of national oppression, and herein she finds the essential
moment or meaning of the nation-state. She is advancing an extremely one-dimensional
account of the formation of the nation-state and its historical significance.
Of course, we donft mean to imply that the bourgeois state does not in
fact suppress ethnic groups within its borders, and as an imperialist state
also dominate other nations. But it is certainly not correct to view the
formation of the bourgeois state as being exclusively determined by this
one aspect. Ultimately, this only confuses the struggles of the working
class and opens the door to reactionary elements.
Luxemburg claims that her own state theory is different from the gconventional
enation-statef ideology.h Here she seems to be referring to bourgeois
liberalism, i.e. the idyllic concept of the democratic and liberal state.
She offers instead a state whose essential moment and content is national
oppression, and in thus a barbaric and reactionary violent state. In this
sense, Luxemburgfs criticism of the state is resolute and without compromise,
although somewhat beside the point. In explaining the difference between
her own concept of the nation-state, which differs from the gconventionalh
concept, she says, gaccording to the bourgeois way of thinking, it is
possible to have a national movement for unification and defense of onefs
own nationality, and at the same time, to oppress another nationality.h
(p. 163) Luxemburg explains this by drawing on the examples of Germany,
Hungary, the Czechs, and Poland. Here it is probably worthwhile to look
at the example of Poland. She says that in seeking the formation of a Polish
nation-state, gPolish bourgeoisie nationalism is directed as much against
the Ruthenians as against the Lithuanians. The very nationality which had
to endure the bitter policy of extermination by the portioning powers?Prussia
and Russia?now refuses the right of independent existence to other nationalities.h
(p. 164) She points out that the same thing can be said for the nationalism
of the Germans and Hungarians. Luxemburg offers the following explanation
of this fact:
This strange double-edged character of bourgeois patriotism, which is essentially
based on the conflicting interests of various nationalities rather than
on harmony, becomes understandable only when one takes into consideration
the fact that the historical basis of the modern national movements of
the bourgeoisie is nothing more than its aspirations to class rule, and
a specific social form in whose aspirations this expression is found: the
modern capitalistic state?gnationalh in the sense of the dominance of
the bourgeoisie of a certain nationality over the entire mixed population
of the state. (pp. 165-6)
This is a very strange idea. On the one hand she says that the modern state
is nationalistic, while on the other hand there is national oppression.
However, this is certainly not a gdouble-edged characterh in the sense
of oppositional meaning, but rather an inevitable outcome of bourgeois
rule, and simply a different expression of this. Bourgeois rule emphasizes
nationalism on the one hand, while assuming a hostile attitude towards
the nationalism of other nationalities, and this stems from this essence.
There is nothing particularly unexpected or strange about this. If Luxemburg
thinks that bourgeois nationalism should adopt a magnanimous attitude towards
the nationalism other countries, then she doesnft understand the reality
of bourgeois nationalism.
The bourgeois state appears in the gnationalh guise because the bourgeoisie
derive a great benefit from incorporating the working class within the
gpeople,h and this nationalism naturally confronts the nationalism of
other countries. This is because they are viewed as nothing but a stubborn
obstacle to national unity. Therefore, in order to understand the essence
of the bourgeois state, first one must first overturn the idea that the
gnationalh in the bourgeois state can be understood as the gdominance
of the bourgeoisie of a certain nationality over the entire mixed population
of the state.h In fact, the gdominanceh of small nationalities stems
from the essence of the bourgeois class state, and so the essence of the
bourgeois state cannot be explained from the gdominanceh of the small
nationalities. However, Luxemburg has this all upside down:
The substance and essence of the modern state compromise not freedom and
independence of the gnation,h but only the class dominance of the bourgeoisie,
protectionist policy, indirect taxation, militarism, war and conquest.
(p. 170)
Luxemburg offers petty bourgeois politicism that has nothing even remotely
in common with Marxism. A superficially grevolutionaryh criticism of
the bourgeois state often masks opportunism. While she fashions the bourgeois
state into a gvillainh by calling it a reactionary state in general,
this is contrasted, on the other hand, with her attempt to create a modern
civilized bourgeois state?the favorite method of liberals. Luxemburg has
forgotten that the bourgeois state also represents the gfreedom and independenceh
of the nation. This is a nation-state for the precise reason that this
is the gfreedomh and gindependenceh for the ruling nation. She has
even forgotten this elementary point. She evaluates the bourgeois state
as only a militaristic and reactionary state?in a word, the imperialistic
state of the stage of monopoly capital?and in contrast to this she recommends
another kind of state that is gfreeh and gindependent.h However, Luxemburg
conceals from the workers that the state she is advocating is also fundamentally
a bourgeois state.
She says that the standpoint of the workers and that of the bourgeois are
fundamentally different, and this is absolutely correct in a sense. However,
the problem centers on the content of this. Luxemburg argues the following:
The national policy of the proletariat, therefore, basically clashes with
the bourgeois policy to the extent that in its essence it is only defensive,
never offensive; it depends on the harmony of interests of all nationalities,
not on conquest and subjugation of one by another. The conscious proletariat
of every country needs for its proper development peaceful existence and
cultural development of its own nationality, but by no means does it need
the dominance of its nationality over others. Therefore, considering the
matter from this point of view, the gnationh-state, as an apparatus of
the domination and conquest of foreign nationalities, while it is indispensable
for the bourgeoisie, has no meaning for the class interests of the proletariat.
Therefore, of these gthree roots of the modern national ideah which Kautsky
enumerated, for the proletariat as a class only the last two are important:
the democratic organizations, and education of the populace. Vital for
the working class, as conditions of its political and spiritual maturity,
are the freedom of using its own native language, and the unchecked and
unwarped development of national culture (learning, literature, the arts)
and normal education of the masses, unimpaired by the pressures of the
nationalists?so far as these can be gnormalh in the bourgeois system.
It is indispensable for the working class to have the same equal national
rights as other nationalities in the state enjoy. Political discrimination
against a particular nationality is the strongest tool in the hands of
the bourgeoisie, which is eager to mask class conflicts and mystify its
own proletariat. (pp. 168-9)
If, on the one hand, political independence, i.e., the nation-state, is
necessary for capitalism and the class interests of the bourgeoisie just
because a nation-state is a tool of domination (or control) and conquest,
on the other hand, the working class is interested in the cultural and
democratic content of nationalism, which is to say that the workers are
interested in such political systems as assure a free development of culture
and democracy in national life by means of defense, not conquest, and in
the spirit of solidarity and cooperation of various nationalities which
belong historically to the same bourgeois state. Equality before the law
for nationalities and political organizations, and the assurance of national
cultural development?such are the general forms of the program of the proletariat,
a natural program resulting from its class position, in contrast to the
nationalism of the bourgeoisie. (p. 175)
These passages expose the essence of Luxemburgfs national policy: i.e.
a reactionary policy almost identical to the Austrian Marxistsf opportunistic
policy of gnational cultural autonomy.h
She contrasts the bourgeois state which is a tool of grule and subjugationh
of other nationalities, to a state realized from a proletarian national
policy which would supposedly be in harmony with other nationalities. However,
is this state really a proletarian state? Fundamentally speaking, this
would not be the case. This would still be a state built on the foundation
of capitalism; a type of bourgeois state. Didnft Luxemburg just say that
the bourgeois state carries out a national policy of grule and subjugationh
precisely because it is a bourgeois state? What right does she have to
say that a bourgeois state would be able to carry out a harmonious and
peaceful national policy? For Luxemburg two types of bourgeois states are
possible, i.e. an goffensive policyh and a gdefensiveh policy.
What is Luxemburg trying to say, exactly? Is she calling for the establishment
of the most democratic state possible in a period of bourgeois revolution
by means of the struggles of the working class? Or is she introducing an
ordinary program of reforming the bourgeois state? Even if we would grant
the favorable interpretation of the former, this doesnft change the fact
that she is raising the question in an extremely vague and mistaken way.
In fact, however, she is standing on the totally opportunistic standpoint
of the Austrian Marxists?the standpoint seeking reforms within the bourgeois
state (the call to defend or strengthen nationalism which is called gnational
cultural autonomyh). Starting from political radicalism, Luxemburg easily
comes approaches and tails after petty bourgeois opportunism.
Incidentally, the idea of gnational cultural autonomyh in the program
of the Austrian Social Democrats was correctly defined by Lenin as nothing
but gshamefacedh or refined nationalism. Under the rule of the bourgeoisie,
liberally diluted nationalism?the idea premised on the existence of various
nations and nationalism while calling for mutual understanding and cooperation,
or the defense of the special rights of gminorityh nations?is not compatible
with the internationalist standpoint of a workers party that unites all
of the working class of a country. Lenin was also clearly opposed the programmatic
standpoint of separate national self-governance or education. But Luxemburg
is in fact advancing the same sort of opportunism.
Rosa Luxemburg and the National Problem: Contents
- Introduction
- The Abstract Denial of Nationalism
- Are the National Tasks Bourgeois Tasks?
- The Theory of the gNation-Stateh and the Class Interests of the Workers
- The gNational Self-Determinationh of Poland
- Centralized Power and Regional Autonomy
- Luxemburgfs Concept of Nation
- Luxemburg Begins to gSelecth or Screen Nations
- National Cultural Autonomy and National Self-Determination
|