MCG top-pageEnglish homepageE-mail

THEORY INDEX

Rosa Luxemburg and the National Problem:
The Similarity of Luxemburgfs Theory
to gAustrian Marxismh

Writen by Hiroyoshi Hayashi (1993)
Translated by Roy West


3. Are the National Tasks Bourgeois Tasks?

A further theoretical basis for Luxemburg opposition to the right of national self-determination was that it gcompletely ignoresh the theory of class society. In other words, it denies gproletarian self-determination.h

When Luxemburg says that the national question has to consider the theory of class society, this means that the national tasks are historical tasks carried out and solved by the bourgeoisie. Of course, this is an undeniable proposition. She says that in capitalistic society there is no question of a gcollective and uniform willh or the self-determination of the gnation,h and that to say this in modern society would amount to pretending that the interests of the bourgeoisie were the interests of the nation as a whole, thereby involving or subsuming the working class within their class interests. The French bourgeoisie carried out the revolution in the name of the people and the German bourgeoisie behaved in the same way in 1848. Thus, the working class should not fight for the slogan of the gpeoplefs rights,h i.e. the defense of the right of national self-determination.

This circumstance shows that the grights of nationsh cannot be a yardstick for the position of the Socialist Party on the nationality question. The very existence of such a party is proof that the bourgeoisie has stopped being the representative of the entire mass of the people, that the class of the proletariat is no longer hidden in the skirts of the bourgeoisie, but has separated itself off as an independent class with its own social and political aspirations. Because the concepts of gnations,h of grights,h and the gwill of the peopleh as a uniform whole are, as we have said, remnants from the time of immature and unconscious antagonism between the proletariat and the bourgeoisie, the application of that idea by the class-conscious and independently organized proletariat would be a striking contradiction?not a contradiction against academic logic, but a historical contradiction. (pp. 137-8)

Therefore, under capitalism the concept of gthe peopleh and the right of national self-determination cannot be the slogan of the working class, since no unified people exist under capitalism, and what exists is rather scattered individuals and opposing social classes. Only socialist society can truly create social ties between these individuals and harmonize their interests, and prior to socialism it is a deception to think that there can be a socially unified will.

Abstractly speaking, Luxemburgfs view is correct. But this was only true at the time in Western Europe and other places where bourgeois society had developed. For the working people living in the many parts of the world stuck in feudalistic conditions and suffering under the rule of foreign imperialism, achieving democracy (one of its forms being self-determination) was certainly not a trivial matter! However, Luxemburg argues that democratic rights in general and the right of self-determination are different.

Therefore, the analogy which is drawn by partisans of the gright of nations to self- determinationh between that grighth and all democratic demands, like the right of free speech, free press, freedom of association and of assembly, is completely incongruous. These people point out that we support the freedom of association because we are the party of political freedom, but we still fight against hostile bourgeois parties. Similarly, they say, we have the democratic duty to support the self-determination of nations, but this fact does not commit us to support every individual tactic of those who fight for self-determination. (p. 139)

In fat, Luxemburg is the one who is being gcompletely incongruous.h That is, she is unable to correctly understand that as a bourgeois right, self-determination has essentially the same historical significance as other bourgeois rights such as the freedom of association or speech. Not only is this a theoretical mistake, but it is also clear that historically the realization of national self-determination in economically backward states is often deeply connected to the achievement of bourgeois democracy. The right of national self-determination is also a bourgeois right?that is, on the basis of capitalism, this means nothing more than that states are formally (i.e. politically) independent, and reciprocally equal and free. Just as bourgeois democracy in general does not deny the rule of monopoly capital, national self-determination does not negate the fact that large states actually rule smaller, weaker states.

Luxemburg lacks this understanding, however. On the one hand, she opposes the right of national self-determination, while on the other hand?as we shall later see in more detail?she seeks a realistic gnationalh policy of the working class. This standpoint of showing a strong aversion to the right of national self-determination, while at he same time seeking a grealistich national policy, are the direct and indirect complementary sides of her theory that form its essence. She opposes the bourgeois slogan of the right of national self-determination with that of the right of proletarian self-determination.

Social Democracy is the class party of the proletariat. Its historical task is to express the class interests of the proletariat and also the revolutionary interests of the development of capitalist society towards realizing socialism. Thus, Social Democracy is called upon to realize not the right of nations to self-determination but only the right of the working class, which is exploited and oppressed, of the proletariat, to self-determination. Form that position Social Democracy examines all social and political questions without exception, and from that standpoint it formulates its programmatic demands. Neither in the question of the political forms which we demand in the state, nor in the questions of law or education, of taxes or the military, does Social Democracy allow the gnationh to decide its fate according to its own vision of self-determination. All of these questions affect the class interests of the proletariat in a way that questions of national-political and national-cultural existence do not. But between those questions and the national-political and national-cultural questions, exist usually the closest ties of mutual dependence and causality. As a result, Social Democracy cannot here escape the necessity of formulating these demands individually, and demanding actively the forms of national-political and national-cultural existence which best corresponds to the interests of the proletariat and its class struggle at a given time and place, as well as to the interests of the revolutionary development of society. Social Democracy cannot leave these questions to be solved by gnationsh. (pp. 140-1).

This is a terribly difficult to understand passage because Luxemburg eliminates bourgeois tasks, such as national self-determination, from the tasks of the proletariat, since this is fundamentally the historical or realistic task of the bourgeoisie, rather than the task of the Social Democratic Party. She makes the extremely general point that the task of the Social Democratic Party is to fight for the interests of the working class. At the same time, however, she says that since gall problemsh are reciprocally related and connected, they should be examined and an effort made to solve them, and that this solution cannot be left up to the nations. Consequently, the Social Democratic Party should naturally make an effort to realistically solve the problem of national self-determination, and there would be no reason to make an exception here.

Luxemburgfs position is not consistent: on the one hand she denies the democratic tasks, while on the other hand addresses them. Luxemburg says that the problem of national self-determination is essentially different from the demands for womenfs equality or the eight-hour workday, and that it is not the same as a bourgeois right, and she seems to start from a strong reaction against nationalism. But, on the other hand, she doesnft show the same reaction towards bourgeois rights in general. This makes her standpoint seem even stranger. In terms of democratic tasks in general, she approves of them as long as they are also an object of the struggles of the working class, but at the same time she is vehemently opposed to the bourgeois right of national self-determination, because it is a bourgeois task and not the task of the workers.

But did Luxemburg rely deny nationalism? What she denied was the right of national self-determination, but on a more profound level didnft she fall into the a conciliatory standpoint towards nationalism?the same theory of gcultural national autonomy as the Austrian Marxists. Wasnft her vehement refusal of national self-determination nothing more than a leftist pose hiding this petty bourgeois program? This is what we shall consider here.

Luxemburgfs so-called gself-determination of the proletariath is exceedingly vague. In the case of the gright of national self-determination,h it is clear that it is historically and politically a question of bourgeois right. Moreover, the gright of national self-determinationh has nothing to do with a situation involving the liberation of the proletariat. What does it mean to speak of the gself-determinationh of the proletariat? Does this mean that the working class obtains political power, rules by itself and realizes socialism? If so, there would be absolutely no need for a vague expression such as gself-determinationh which leads to confusion. In such a case it would be clear from the beginning that the working class had gained power. In other words, when raising the question of national self-determination, this presupposes the case of bourgeois emancipation, whereas gself-determinationh does not become an issue in the case of the liberation of the working class. Of course, this is distinguished conceptually, but in practice things are more complex. For example, the profound emancipation of a country (equality) can only be realized in connection to socialism, but at that stage it is already not a question of the liberation of the nation (equality), but the sublation of the nation?i.e. the question of which gnationh people belong to already loses its essential social significance and becomes irrelevant!

Those who contrast the gright of self-determinationh of the working class to the right of national self-determination, and in this way believe that latter is gnot realistich or can somehow be negated, have failed to understand the essence of the problem. Unfortunately Rosa Luxemburg is one of these people.

Luxemburg denied the right of national self-determination for Poland, in the sense that she thought that it should not be held up in general as the slogan of national self-determination for the Russian Social Democratic Party. She cites the example of someone who said that it was all right for the Russian party to call for national self-determination, but not for the Polish party to do this, as an example of the duality or schizophrenia of the Social Democratic Party. For her, this argument shows that it is a mistake for workers to raise the slogan of national self-determination. The Polish Social Democratic Party, as one part of the Russian Social Democratic Party, should not have a different programmatic standpoint than that of the Russian party as a whole, but the Russian party raised the demand of the right of self-determination, while the Polish party, if it wishes to have a class program different from that of the demands of bourgeois nationalists in Poland, would have to be in contradiction with this standpoint, and this would split or weaken the line of the Social Democratic Party which should be united.

Thus, Social Democracy of all Russia, united both in ideas and factually, has two different propositions. As a whole, it stands for the gnationsh; in its constituent parts, it stands for the separate proletariat of each nation. But these positions can be quite different and may even be completely opposed to each other. (pp. 147-8)

However, the fact that the Russian party members?i.e. those members belonging to the oppressing nation?should raise the right of national self-determination, while those in the Polish party should not does not mean that they are greciprocally opposedh (quite the opposite!), since the national program is one part of the Social Democratic Party program, and not everything, and that this does not deny in the least that within the framework of their general commonality, the Social Democratic parties within each country might raise independent slogans depending on the particular nature of the objective situation in which they are placed.


Rosa Luxemburg and the National Problem: Contents
  1. Introduction
  2. The Abstract Denial of Nationalism
  3. Are the National Tasks Bourgeois Tasks?
  4. The Theory of the gNation-Stateh and the Class Interests of the Workers
  5. The gNational Self-Determinationh of Poland
  6. Centralized Power and Regional Autonomy
  7. Luxemburgfs Concept of Nation
  8. Luxemburg Begins to gSelecth or Screen Nations
  9. National Cultural Autonomy and National Self-Determination


Zenkokushakensha
Zip:179-0074, 1-11-12-409 Kasuga-chou Nerima-ku Tokyo Japan
tel/fax +81-3(6795)2822

E-mail to WPLL
TOP