MCG top-pageEnglish homepageE-mail

THEORY INDEX

Rosa Luxemburg and the National Problem:
The Similarity of Luxemburgfs Theory
to gAustrian Marxismh

Writen by Hiroyoshi Hayashi (1993)
Translated by Roy West


6. Centralized Power and Regional Autonomy

For Luxemburg, the question of the relationship between centralized power and regional autonomy is a central concern. This is because this was deeply connected to the question of the possibility or realization of the gnational cultural autonomyh of Poland. She developed her view of this relationship by criticizing Kautsky.

The characteristic of Kautskyfs theory was the distinction between the centralization of gadministrationh and the centralization of the glegislative process.h As a Marxist, he is a defender of centralization, but what he defended was the centralization of glegislation,h not the gcentralization of administrationh. This is because he saw the latter as the deed of feudalistic absolutism or counter-revolution, and had no relation to democracy. On the other hand, the centralization of legislation is different from that of administration, and is a democratic form. Along with the unification of laws, there arises ga striving for decentralization of administration of the provinces and communes.h Therefore, Kautsky recognizes the centralization of legislative rights, but refuses that for local autonomy. To put it more schematically: Kautsky opposes to central and regional government, as well as regional assembles, while on the other hand he defends centralized legislature and regional government autonomy (without legislative power). The legislative power and parliament would be centralized, while the administrative power would be regional. Kautsky felt that this would be a state system that would be able to secure democratic centralized rights, while at the same time responding to the particularities of each region. Of course, this is a classic example of a dogmatic and formulaic theory.

Luxemburg was not principally opposed to Kautskyfs centralization, and in fact highly praises his theory:

Kautskyfs arguments are in their essence extremely valuable as an indication concerning the general tendency in Social Democratic policy, concerning its basic standpoint towards centralism and big-power policy on the on hand and particularistic tendencies on the other. (p. 250)

Despite this, she criticized Kautsky because his view denied or limited the legislative rights of regional governments.

Luxemburg defended the concept that regional government was not only a question of finances, but also had the task of solving certain social problems in the local areas.

On the other hand, autonomy itself puts up barriers to legislative centralization, because without certain legislative competences, even narrowly outlined and purely local, no self-government is possible. The power of issuing within a certain sphere, on its own initiative, laws binding for the population, and not merely supervising the execution of laws issued by the central legislative body, constitutes precisely the soul and core of self-government in the modern democratic sense?it forms the basic function of municipal and communal councils as well as of provincial diets or departmental councils. (p. 248)

In this way, Luxemburg one-dimensionally criticized Kautskyfs theory for excluding the legislative rights of local assemblies:

This can be done, in our opinion, not by a formulistic approach, whereby the legislative and the administrative powers are separated, but by separating some spheres of social life?namely those which constitute the core of a capitalist economy and of a bourgeois state?from the sphere of local interests. (p. 249)

Thus, Luxemburg thinks that the glocal interestsh can be widened, and hidden beneath this is the aim for gnational self-governmenth that overcomes the problem of local self-government. In other words, she thinks that, gprecisely from the same foundations from which, in all capitalistic states, grows local self-government, there also grows in certain conditions national autonomy.h (p. 250)

As we have seen, the requirements of the capitalist system lead with historic necessity in all modern states to the development of local self-government through the participation of the people in carrying out sociopolitical functions on all levels, from the commune to the district and province. Where, however, inside a modern state there exist distinct nationality districts constituting at the same time territories with certain economic and social distinctions, the same requirements of the bourgeois economy make self-government on the highest, country-wide level, indispensable. On this level, local self-government is also transformed, as a result of a new factor, national-cultural distinctness, into a special type of democratic institution applicable only in quite specific conditions. (p. 256)

To anticipate our argument a bit, this passage shows the characteristic of Luxemburgfs opinion, as well as exposes her theoretical confusion. On the one hand, she argues for geconomic and social autonomyh for Poland, but she completely denies Polish geconomic independence,h and emphasizes how economically dependent Poland is upon Russia. She really wants to speak of gnational and cultural autonomy,h not geconomic autonomy,h but in order to speak of the former she is obliged to bring up the question of economic autonomy, and in this way she exposes the absence of any real foundation for her own theory.

We should also pay attention to her statement about gdomestic self-government as the highest level of self-government.h She positions this from gbourgeois economic demands.h Of course, here gdomestic self-governmenth is used in almost the same sense as gnational autonomy.h In other words, she views gnational self-governmenth as the ghighesth self-government, but emphasizes that this is a demand of bourgeois rule, or completely indemnified from this. This not only opens the way for petty bourgeois nationalism, but also spreads fantasies towards bourgeois democracy. Herein lies the Luxemburgfs thorough opportunism.

The reason that Luxemburg discusses gcentralization and local self-governmenth at length, is precisely to theoretically position the demand for Polish gnational self-government.h Here we will look concretely at how she posits this.

Luxemburg emphasizes self-government in Poland?she uses such terms as regional self-government and domestic self-government?but this was definitely not the demand for national self-determination (i.e. the formation of a national state) in Poland. Instead, this was the call for autonomy or national self-government within the boundaries of a Russian republic. On this point, Luxemburg opposed the nationalism of Poland, on the one hand, while secretly introducing it on the other hand (in the same manner as all of the theorists of gcultural and national autonomyh!). Luxemburgfs rational for doing this is strange, but before looking at this, letfs look at how she connected the rule of the bourgeoisie in Poland with national self-government.

According to Luxemburg, gnational autonomy of the Kingdom of Polandh is primarily a demand of the Polish bourgeoisie, which seeks to gstrengthen its class rule and to develop its institutions in order to exploit and oppress with no restrictions whatsoever,h (p. 258), but on the other hand this is also necessary for as the gmost mature political form of bourgeois rule.h Of course, when compared to the totality of the Russian state, gnational autonomyh has a narrow range, but within this it is an indispensable tool of bourgeois class rule as one part of the gmodern state-political parliamentary institutions.h Luxemburg says:

Political liberty and self-government will eventually give the Polish bourgeoisie the possibility of utilizing a number of presently neglected social functions?schools, religious worship, and the entire cultural-spiritual life of the country?for its own class interests. By manning all offices of the administration, judiciary, and politics, the bourgeoisie will be able to assimilate genuinely these natural organs of class rule with the spirit and home needs of bourgeois society, and so turn them into flexible, accurate, and subtle tools of the Polish ruling classes. Natural autonomy, as a part of all-state political freedom, is, in a word, the most mature political form of bourgeois rule in Poland. (p. 258)

When this passage is examined, it reveals a strange content. That is, she says that political liberty will allow the Polish bourgeoisie to connect the state power as a tool of class rule to the gspirith of bourgeois society, but it is incomprehensible why the word gspirith appears here. We can grasp the idea that the state apparatus as a tool of old class rule, would be transformed into a tool of the bourgeoisie under their class rule, but it is extremely difficult to rationally understand what she means by saying that under bourgeois rule the state apparatus would be gassimilated with the spirith of this rule. But this is certainly not a random or simple gmistakeh, as we shall see later. Putting this aside, however, the conclusions that Luxemburg draws from this assumption in terms of the program and policy of the workers are absurd, and only further expose the limitations of her theory:

However, precisely for this reason, autonomy is an indispensable class need of the Polish proletariat. The riper the bourgeois institutions grow, the deeper they penetrate the social functions, the more ground they cover within the variegated intellectual and aesthetic sphere, the broader grows the battlefield and the bigger the number of firing lines wherefrom the proletariat conducts the class struggle. The more unrestrictedly and efficiently the development of bourgeois society proceeds, the more courageously and surely advances the consciousness, political maturity, and unification of the proletariat as a class.

The Polish proletariat needs for its class struggle all the components of which a spiritual culture is made; primarily, its interests, essentially based on the solidarity of nations and striving towards it, require the elimination of national oppression, and guarantees against such oppression worked out in the course of social development. Moreover, a normal, broad, and unrestricted cultural life of the country is just as indispensable for the development of the proletariatfs class struggle as for the existence of bourgeois society itself.

National autonomy has the same aims as are contained in the political program of the Polish proletariat: the overthrow of absolutism and the achievement of political freedom in the country at large; this is but a part of the program resulting both from the progressive trends of capitalist development and from the class interests of the proletariat. (p. 259)

Here we have the opportunistic idea that bourgeois development will be in the workers own class interests. Luxemburg abstracts gspiritual and cultural lifeh from bourgeois development, and by treating this one-dimensionally spreads the idea that this is in the interests of the workers, or the Polish nation as a whole. Her difference from other nationalists is that that this is not expressed in naked terms, and is instead hidden behind ambiguous terms such as gnational autonomy.h But if this were expressed clearly there would be no difference from other nationalists. It is true that she does not introduce national self-determination, but in a concealed form she essentially proposes the same thing. What is worse, unlike Lenin she does not make it clear that self-determination is one form of bourgeois democracy, and thereby renders vague the decisively important practical point that this for the working class this demand is historically limited. Even when Lenin defended national self-determination, he never blurred its historical and class content. For Lenin, national self-determination was one part of bourgeois democracy, and therefore once this democracy had been achieved it immediately became a reactionary slogan which should be unconditionally opposed by the working class. Luxemburgfs gnational autonomy,h on the other hand, believes that it is necessary to hold on to nationalistic pipe dreams even after bourgeois rule has been established!

Luxemburg aspired for a revolution throughout the Russian empire to overthrow Czarism, and lead to democracy in Poland as well. At the same time, this was supposed to make possible gnational autonomy,h i.e. gnational cultural autonomy,h and she said that this would be in the interests of the class struggles of the workers. She felt that development of class struggles would need gall the components of which a spiritual culture is made,h and that the most important of these is the unrestricted development of a national culture. At best, this is what Luxemburg means when she speaks of the gindependent national program of the working class.h

If Luxemburg recognizes that the interests of the working class require gthe elimination of national oppression, and guarantees against such oppression worked out in the course of social development,h (p. 259), she would have to recognize the significance of national self-determination. However, while basically recognizing the significance of the development of class struggles, but theoretically she denies its significance, and does not even seem to be aware of the extent of her own self-contradictions. In fact, it wouldnft be strange at all if what Luxemburg calls gnational autonomyh were in fact national self-determination. Her gnational self-determinationh has almost the same content as the right of national self-determination. Nevertheless, she stubbornly denied that this was the same thing. She wants to say that national self-determination is nationalistic, but gnational autonomyh is not. But is this indeed the case? How can it be said that gnational autonomyh is not nationalistic?

In fact, Luxemburgfs gnational autonomyh or gnational cultural autonomyh are in fact completely nationalistic. The only difference is that the demand for national self-determination is recognized as having a bourgeois nature, and only being part of the program of the working class under certain conditions, whereas gnational cultural autonomyh appeared as a petty bourgeois slogan from the beginning. The latter is a petty bourgeois demand under the rule of capital that represents liberal deception. Luxemburg and others forget the reactionary meaning of raising one of the democratic tasks (i.e. national program) after the bourgeois democratic tasks have been fundamentally solved. Under bourgeois democracy, it is not the national moment, but rather class principles that must be raised and emphasized. Luxemburg, however, exposes her own opportunism by saying that the national program can regain its true meaning by means of the realization of bourgeois democracy. This is precisely the gextreme theoretical weaknessh (Lenin) of Luxemburg. The formation of the nation state and the realization of democracy represent the fundamental solution of the national problem as a historical task. Therefore, after this point, national slogans become reactionary, and in their place the emphasis should be placed on the class slogans. In this situation, however, Luxemburg instead says that the nationalistic slogans are fundamental. This causes unbelievable confusion and is nothing but pure opportunism.

Isnft it clear that if the Czarist system were eliminated in the Russian Empire (including Poland) and democracy established, that this would also represent the solution of the national problem? The recognition of the right to self-determination would be part of this, i.e. the likely national liberation of Poland and Finland and the political equality of all of the people in the Russian empire. In short, principally speaking, it would be clear that this democratic revolution would fundamentally solve the national problem?this does not mean, however, that this problem will in fact be permanently eliminated. In reality, even with the realization of democracy various forms of gnational discriminationh remain. However, we need to recognize the significance that at least legally speaking gnational discriminationh is removed, and all of the citizens have equal rights. It is important to recognize this because from this stage, the ultimate task of the workers?of all nationalities?is not the national problem, but rather the problem of class conflict. The nationalists, liberals, citizen groups and opportunists will continue to focus on the focus on the gnational problem,h but for workers this is a problem with only secondary significance, increasingly subsumed within the class problem. It is completely petty bourgeois and opportunistic to say that the question of national autonomy remains an essential problem even after the bourgeois democratic state has been established.

Even at first sight, Luxemburgfs opinion is strange. On the on the hand, she attacks the right of self-determination as bourgeois, from an abstract standpoint of an extreme internationalism. (Lenin, incidentally, was extremely of this aspect of her theory.) But in fact her position was an extremely nationalistic one because she said that the nationalistic standpoint was still important even after bourgeois democracy had triumphed?and indeed more so in this case!?and that indeed at this stage nationalism (although this is defined as gspiritual cultureh) for the first time comes to take on decisive significance. It seems that Luxemburg noisily attacks the right of self-determination on the surface only in order to secretly introduce petty bourgeois nationalism at the same time.


Rosa Luxemburg and the National Problem: Contents
  1. Introduction
  2. The Abstract Denial of Nationalism
  3. Are the National Tasks Bourgeois Tasks?
  4. The Theory of the gNation-Stateh and the Class Interests of the Workers
  5. The gNational Self-Determinationh of Poland
  6. Centralized Power and Regional Autonomy
  7. Luxemburgfs Concept of Nation
  8. Luxemburg Begins to gSelecth or Screen Nations
  9. National Cultural Autonomy and National Self-Determination


Zenkokushakensha
Zip:179-0074, 1-11-12-409 Kasuga-chou Nerima-ku Tokyo Japan
tel/fax +81-3(6795)2822

E-mail to WPLL
TOP